If you're seeing this message, it means we're having trouble loading external resources on our website.

If you're behind a web filter, please make sure that the domains *.kastatic.org and *.kasandbox.org are unblocked.

To log in and use all the features of Khan Academy, please enable JavaScript in your browser.

AP®︎/College Biology

Course: ap®︎/college biology   >   unit 7.

  • Introduction to evolution and natural selection
  • Natural selection and the owl butterfly
  • Biodiversity and natural selection
  • Variation in a species

Darwin, evolution, & natural selection

Natural selection, key points:.

  • Charles Darwin was a British naturalist who proposed the theory of biological evolution by natural selection.
  • Darwin defined evolution as "descent with modification," the idea that species change over time, give rise to new species, and share a common ancestor.
  • The mechanism that Darwin proposed for evolution is natural selection . Because resources are limited in nature, organisms with heritable traits that favor survival and reproduction will tend to leave more offspring than their peers, causing the traits to increase in frequency over generations.
  • Natural selection causes populations to become adapted , or increasingly well-suited, to their environments over time. Natural selection depends on the environment and requires existing heritable variation in a group.

What is evolution?

Early ideas about evolution, influences on darwin, darwin and the voyage of the beagle.

  • Traits are often heritable. In living organisms, many characteristics are inherited, or passed from parent to offspring. (Darwin knew this was the case, even though he did not know that traits were inherited via genes.) A diagram with text reading parents pass on heritable traits to their offspring. On the left a dark blue and a light blue butterfly are crossed to produce offspring with wings of varying shades of blue. On the right a dark red and a light red butterfly are crossed to produce offspring with wings of varying shades of red.
  • More offspring are produced than can survive. Organisms are capable of producing more offspring than their environments can support. Thus, there is competition for limited resources in each generation. A diagram with a box reading limited resources. Arrows point away from the box to bubbles reading lack of food, lack of habitat, and lack of mates. Text below reads …not all individuals will survive and reproduce. A group of 16 butterflies with wings of varying shades of blue and red is shown. A text bubble reading gleep! comes from 4 of the butterflies.
  • Offspring vary in their heritable traits. The offspring in any generation will be slightly different from one another in their traits (color, size, shape, etc.), and many of these features will be heritable. A group of 16 butterflies with wings of varying shades of blue and red is shown. A text bubble reading Hey, are you red? That's pretty sweet! comes from one of the blue butterflies. A text bubble reading Whoa! Love that blue wing color comes from one of the red butterflies. Text at the bottom reads Butterflies do not actually talk! Cartoon for cute illustration purposes only. A smiley face is shown next to the text.
  • In a population, some individuals will have inherited traits that help them survive and reproduce (given the conditions of the environment, such as the predators and food sources present). The individuals with the helpful traits will leave more offspring in the next generation than their peers, since the traits make them more effective at surviving and reproducing.
  • Because the helpful traits are heritable, and because organisms with these traits leave more offspring, the traits will tend to become more common (present in a larger fraction of the population) in the next generation.
  • Over generations, the population will become adapted to its environment (as individuals with traits helpful in that environment have consistently greater reproductive success than their peers).

Example: How natural selection can work

Key points about natural selection, natural selection depends on the environment, natural selection acts on existing heritable variation, heritable variation comes from random mutations, natural selection and the evolution of species, attribution:, works cited:.

  • Wilkin, D. and Akre, B. (2016, March 23). Influences on Darwin - Advanced. In CK-12 biology advanced concepts . Retrieved from http://www.ck12.org/book/CK-12-Biology-Advanced-Concepts/section/10.18/ .
  • Reece, J. B., Urry, L. A., Cain, M. L., Wasserman, S. A., Minorsky, P. V., and Jackson, R. B. (2011). The voyage of the Beagle . In Campbell Biology (10th ed., p. 466). San Francisco, CA: Pearson.
  • Darwin's finches. (2016, April 25). Retrieved March 16, 2016 from Wikipedia: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Darwin%27s_finches .
  • Reece, J. B., Urry, L. A., Cain, M. L., Wasserman, S. A., Minorsky, P. V., and Jackson, R. B. (2011). Figure 1.18. Natural selection. In Campbell biology (10th ed., p. 14). San Francisco, CA: Pearson.

Additional references:

Want to join the conversation.

  • Upvote Button navigates to signup page
  • Downvote Button navigates to signup page
  • Flag Button navigates to signup page

Great Answer

  • Support Our Work

The Smithsonian Institution's Human Origins Program

  • Introduction to Human Evolution

3/4 view of an early human skull

Human evolution

Human evolution is the lengthy process of change by which people originated from apelike ancestors. Scientific evidence shows that the physical and behavioral traits shared by all people originated from apelike ancestors and evolved over a period of approximately six million years.

One of the earliest defining human traits, bipedalism -- the ability to walk on two legs -- evolved over 4 million years ago. Other important human characteristics -- such as a large and complex brain, the ability to make and use tools, and the capacity for language -- developed more recently. Many advanced traits -- including complex symbolic expression, art, and elaborate cultural diversity -- emerged mainly during the past 100,000 years.

Humans are primates. Physical and genetic similarities show that the modern human species, Homo sapiens , has a very close relationship to another group of primate species, the apes. Humans and the great apes (large apes) of Africa -- chimpanzees (including bonobos, or so-called “pygmy chimpanzees”) and gorillas -- share a common ancestor that lived between 8 and 6 million years ago. Humans first evolved in Africa, and much of human evolution occurred on that continent. The fossils of early humans who lived between 6 and 2 million years ago come entirely from Africa.

Most scientists currently recognize some 15 to 20 different species of early humans. Scientists do not all agree, however, about how these species are related or which ones simply died out. Many early human species -- certainly the majority of them – left no living descendants. Scientists also debate over how to identify and classify particular species of early humans, and about what factors influenced the evolution and extinction of each species.

Early humans first migrated out of Africa into Asia probably between 2 million and 1.8 million years ago. They entered Europe somewhat later, between 1.5 million and 1 million years. Species of modern humans populated many parts of the world much later. For instance, people first came to Australia probably within the past 60,000 years and to the Americas within the past 30,000 years or so. The beginnings of agriculture and the rise of the first civilizations occurred within the past 12,000 years.

Paleoanthropology

Paleoanthropology is the scientific study of human evolution. Paleoanthropology is a subfield of anthropology, the study of human culture, society, and biology. The field involves an understanding of the similarities and differences between humans and other species in their genes, body form, physiology, and behavior. Paleoanthropologists search for the roots of human physical traits and behavior. They seek to discover how evolution has shaped the potentials, tendencies, and limitations of all people. For many people, paleoanthropology is an exciting scientific field because it investigates the origin, over millions of years, of the universal and defining traits of our species. However, some people find the concept of human evolution troubling because it can seem not to fit with religious and other traditional beliefs about how people, other living things, and the world came to be. Nevertheless, many people have come to reconcile their beliefs with the scientific evidence.

Early human fossils and archeological remains offer the most important clues about this ancient past. These remains include bones, tools and any other evidence (such as footprints, evidence of hearths, or butchery marks on animal bones) left by earlier people. Usually, the remains were buried and preserved naturally. They are then found either on the surface (exposed by rain, rivers, and wind erosion) or by digging in the ground. By studying fossilized bones, scientists learn about the physical appearance of earlier humans and how it changed. Bone size, shape, and markings left by muscles tell us how those predecessors moved around, held tools, and how the size of their brains changed over a long time. Archeological evidence refers to the things earlier people made and the places where scientists find them. By studying this type of evidence, archeologists can understand how early humans made and used tools and lived in their environments.

The process of evolution

The process of evolution involves a series of natural changes that cause species (populations of different organisms) to arise, adapt to the environment, and become extinct. All species or organisms have originated through the process of biological evolution. In animals that reproduce sexually, including humans, the term species refers to a group whose adult members regularly interbreed, resulting in fertile offspring -- that is, offspring themselves capable of reproducing. Scientists classify each species with a unique, two-part scientific name. In this system, modern humans are classified as Homo sapiens .

Evolution occurs when there is change in the genetic material -- the chemical molecule, DNA -- which is inherited from the parents, and especially in the proportions of different genes in a population. Genes represent the segments of DNA that provide the chemical code for producing proteins. Information contained in the DNA can change by a process known as mutation. The way particular genes are expressed – that is, how they influence the body or behavior of an organism -- can also change. Genes affect how the body and behavior of an organism develop during its life, and this is why genetically inherited characteristics can influence the likelihood of an organism’s survival and reproduction.

Evolution does not change any single individual. Instead, it changes the inherited means of growth and development that typify a population (a group of individuals of the same species living in a particular habitat). Parents pass adaptive genetic changes to their offspring, and ultimately these changes become common throughout a population. As a result, the offspring inherit those genetic characteristics that enhance their chances of survival and ability to give birth, which may work well until the environment changes. Over time, genetic change can alter a species' overall way of life, such as what it eats, how it grows, and where it can live. Human evolution took place as new genetic variations in early ancestor populations favored new abilities to adapt to environmental change and so altered the human way of life.

Dr. Rick Potts provides a video short introduction to some of the evidence for human evolution, in the form of fossils and artifacts.

  • Climate Effects on Human Evolution
  • Survival of the Adaptable
  • Human Evolution Timeline Interactive
  • 2011 Olorgesailie Dispatches
  • 2004 Olorgesailie Dispatches
  • 1999 Olorgesailie Dispatches
  • Olorgesailie Drilling Project
  • Kanam, Kenya
  • Kanjera, Kenya
  • Ol Pejeta, Kenya
  • Olorgesailie, Kenya
  • Evolution of Human Innovation
  • Adventures in the Rift Valley: Interactive
  • 'Hobbits' on Flores, Indonesia
  • Earliest Humans in China
  • Bose, China
  • Anthropocene: The Age of Humans
  • Fossil Forensics: Interactive
  • What's Hot in Human Origins?
  • Instructions
  • Carnivore Dentition
  • Ungulate Dentition
  • Primate Behavior
  • Footprints from Koobi Fora, Kenya
  • Laetoli Footprint Trails
  • Footprints from Engare Sero, Tanzania
  • Hammerstone from Majuangou, China
  • Handaxe and Tektites from Bose, China
  • Handaxe from Europe
  • Handaxe from India
  • Oldowan Tools from Lokalalei, Kenya
  • Olduvai Chopper
  • Stone Tools from Majuangou, China
  • Middle Stone Age Tools
  • Burin from Laugerie Haute & Basse, Dordogne, France
  • La Madeleine, Dordogne, France
  • Butchered Animal Bones from Gona, Ethiopia
  • Katanda Bone Harpoon Point
  • Oldest Wooden Spear
  • Punctured Horse Shoulder Blade
  • Stone Sickle Blades
  • Projectile Point
  • Oldest Pottery
  • Pottery Fragment
  • Fire-Altered Stone Tools
  • Terra Amata Shelter
  • Qafzeh: Oldest Intentional Burial
  • Assyrian Cylinder Seal
  • Blombos Ocher Plaque
  • Ishango Bone
  • Bone and Ivory Needles
  • Carved Ivory Running Lion
  • Female torso in ivory
  • Ivory Horse Figurine
  • Ivory Horse Sculpture
  • Lady of Brassempouy
  • Lion-Man Figurine
  • Willendorf Venus
  • Ancient Shell Beads
  • Carved Bone Disc
  • Cro-Magnon Shell Bead Necklace
  • Oldest Known Shell Beads
  • Ancient Flute
  • Ancient Pigments
  • Apollo 11 Plaque
  • Carved antler baton with horses
  • Geometric incised bone rectangle
  • Tata Plaque
  • Mystery Skull Interactive
  • Shanidar 3 - Neanderthal Skeleton
  • One Species, Living Worldwide
  • Human Skin Color Variation
  • Ancient DNA and Neanderthals
  • Human Family Tree
  • Swartkrans, South Africa
  • Shanidar, Iraq
  • Walking Upright
  • Tools & Food
  • Social Life
  • Language & Symbols
  • Humans Change the World
  • Nuts and bolts classification: Arbitrary or not? (Grades 6-8)
  • Comparison of Human and Chimp Chromosomes (Grades 9-12)
  • Hominid Cranial Comparison: The "Skulls" Lab (Grades 9-12)
  • Investigating Common Descent: Formulating Explanations and Models (Grades 9-12)
  • Fossil and Migration Patterns in Early Hominids (Grades 9-12)
  • For College Students
  • Why do we get goose bumps?
  • Chickens, chimpanzees, and you - what do they have in common?
  • Grandparents are unique to humans
  • How strong are we?
  • Humans are handy!
  • Humans: the running ape
  • Our big hungry brain!
  • Our eyes say it!
  • The early human tool kit
  • The short-haired human!
  • The “Nutcracker”
  • What can lice tell us about human evolution?
  • What does gut got to do with it?
  • Why do paleoanthropologists love Lucy?
  • Why do we have wisdom teeth?
  • Human Origins Glossary
  • Teaching Evolution through Human Examples
  • Frequently Asked Questions
  • Recommended Books
  • Exhibit Floorplan Interactive
  • Print Floorplan PDF
  • Reconstructions of Early Humans
  • Chesterfield County Public Library
  • Orange County Library
  • Andover Public Library
  • Ephrata Public Library
  • Oelwein Public Library
  • Cedar City Public Library
  • Milpitas Library
  • Spokane County Library
  • Cottage Grove Public Library
  • Pueblo City-County Library
  • Springfield-Greene County Library
  • Peoria Public Library
  • Orion Township Public Library
  • Skokie Public Library
  • Wyckoff Free Public Library
  • Tompkins County Public Library
  • Otis Library
  • Fletcher Free Library
  • Bangor Public Library
  • Human Origins Do it Yourself Exhibit
  • Exhibit Field Trip Guide
  • Acknowledgments
  • Human Origins Program Team
  • Connie Bertka
  • Betty Holley
  • Nancy Howell
  • Lee Meadows
  • Jamie L. Jensen
  • David Orenstein
  • Michael Tenneson
  • Leonisa Ardizzone
  • David Haberman
  • Fred Edwords (Emeritus)
  • Elliot Dorff (Emeritus)
  • Francisca Cho (Emeritus)
  • Peter F. Ryan (Emeritus)
  • Mustansir Mir (Emeritus)
  • Randy Isaac (Emeritus)
  • Mary Evelyn Tucker (Emeritus)
  • Wentzel van Huyssteen (Emeritus)
  • Joe Watkins (Emeritus)
  • Tom Weinandy (Emeritus)
  • Members Thoughts on Science, Religion & Human Origins (video)
  • Science, Religion, Evolution and Creationism: Primer
  • The Evolution of Religious Belief: Seeking Deep Evolutionary Roots
  • Laboring for Science, Laboring for Souls:  Obstacles and Approaches to Teaching and Learning Evolution in the Southeastern United States
  • Public Event : Religious Audiences and the Topic of Evolution: Lessons from the Classroom (video)
  • Evolution and the Anthropocene: Science, Religion, and the Human Future
  • Imagining the Human Future: Ethics for the Anthropocene
  • Human Evolution and Religion: Questions and Conversations from the Hall of Human Origins
  • I Came from Where? Approaching the Science of Human Origins from Religious Perspectives
  • Religious Perspectives on the Science of Human Origins
  • Submit Your Response to "What Does It Mean To Be Human?"
  • Volunteer Opportunities
  • Submit Question
  • "Shaping Humanity: How Science, Art, and Imagination Help Us Understand Our Origins" (book by John Gurche)
  • What Does It Mean To Be Human? (book by Richard Potts and Chris Sloan)
  • Bronze Statues
  • Reconstructed Faces

Loading metrics

Open Access

Essays articulate a specific perspective on a topic of broad interest to scientists.

See all article types »

How Could Language Have Evolved?

* E-mail: [email protected]

Affiliations Cognitive Neurobiology and Helmholtz Institute, Departments of Psychology and Biology, Utrecht University, Utrecht, The Netherlands, Department of Zoology and Sidney Sussex College, University of Cambridge, Cambridge, United Kingdom

Affiliation Division of Anthropology, American Museum of Natural History, New York, New York, United States of America

Affiliation Department of Linguistics and Philosophy, MIT, Cambridge, Massachusetts, United States of America

Affiliation Department of Electrical Engineering & Computer Science and Brain and Cognitive Sciences, MIT, Cambridge, Massachusetts, United States of America

  • Johan J. Bolhuis, 
  • Ian Tattersall, 
  • Noam Chomsky, 
  • Robert C. Berwick

PLOS

Published: August 26, 2014

  • https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pbio.1001934
  • Reader Comments

Figure 1

The evolution of the faculty of language largely remains an enigma. In this essay, we ask why. Language's evolutionary analysis is complicated because it has no equivalent in any nonhuman species. There is also no consensus regarding the essential nature of the language “phenotype.” According to the “Strong Minimalist Thesis,” the key distinguishing feature of language (and what evolutionary theory must explain) is hierarchical syntactic structure. The faculty of language is likely to have emerged quite recently in evolutionary terms, some 70,000–100,000 years ago, and does not seem to have undergone modification since then, though individual languages do of course change over time, operating within this basic framework. The recent emergence of language and its stability are both consistent with the Strong Minimalist Thesis, which has at its core a single repeatable operation that takes exactly two syntactic elements a and b and assembles them to form the set {a, b}.

Citation: Bolhuis JJ, Tattersall I, Chomsky N, Berwick RC (2014) How Could Language Have Evolved? PLoS Biol 12(8): e1001934. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pbio.1001934

Copyright: © 2014 Bolhuis et al. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License , which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author and source are credited.

Funding: JJB is funded by Utrecht University and by Netherlands Organization for Scientific Research (NWO) grants (ALW Open Competition and NWO Gravity and Horizon Programmes) ( http://www.nwo.nl/ ). The funders had no role in study design, data collection and analysis, decision to publish, or preparation of the manuscript.

Competing interests: The authors have declared that no competing interests exist.

It is uncontroversial that language has evolved, just like any other trait of living organisms. That is, once—not so long ago in evolutionary terms—there was no language at all, and now there is, at least in Homo sapiens . There is considerably less agreement as to how language evolved. There are a number of reasons for this lack of agreement. First, “language” is not always clearly defined, and this lack of clarity regarding the language phenotype leads to a corresponding lack of clarity regarding its evolutionary origins. Second, there is often confusion as to the nature of the evolutionary process and what it can tell us about the mechanisms of language. Here we argue that the basic principle that underlies language's hierarchical syntactic structure is consistent with a relatively recent evolutionary emergence.

Conceptualizations of Language

The language faculty is often equated with “communication”—a trait that is shared by all animal species and possibly also by plants. In our view, for the purposes of scientific understanding, language should be understood as a particular computational cognitive system, implemented neurally, that cannot be equated with an excessively expansive notion of “language as communication” [1] . Externalized language may be used for communication, but that particular function is largely irrelevant in this context. Thus, the origin of the language faculty does not generally seem to be informed by considerations of the evolution of communication. This viewpoint does not preclude the possibility that communicative considerations can play a role in accounting for the maintenance of language once it has appeared or for the historical language change that has clearly occurred within the human species, with all individuals sharing a common language faculty, as some mathematical models indicate [1] – [3] . A similar misconception is that language is coextensive with speech and that the evolution of vocalization or auditory-vocal learning can therefore inform us about the evolution of language ( Box 1 ) [1] , [4] . However, speech and speech perception, while functioning as possible external interfaces for the language system, are not identical to it. An alternative externalization of language is in the visual domain, as sign language [1] ; even haptic externalization by touch seems possible in deaf and blind individuals [5] . Thus, while the evolution of auditory-vocal learning may be relevant for the evolution of speech, it is not for the language faculty per se. We maintain that language is a computational cognitive mechanism that has hierarchical syntactic structure at its core [1] , as outlined in the next section.

Box 1. Comparative Linguistics: Not Much to Compare

A major stumbling block for the comparative analysis of language evolution is that, so far, there is no evidence for human-like language syntax in any nonhuman species [4] , [41] , [42] . There is no a priori reason why a version of such a combinatorial computational system could not have evolved in nonhuman animals, either through common descent (e.g., apes) or convergent evolution (e.g., songbirds) [1] , [18] . Although the auditory-vocal domain is just one possible external interface for language (with signing being another), it could be argued that the strongest animal candidates for human-like syntax are songbirds and parrots [1] , [41] , [42] . Not only do they have a similar brain organization underlying auditory-vocal behavior [4] , [43] , [44] , they also exhibit vocal imitation learning that proceeds in a very similar way to speech acquisition in human infants [4] , [41] , [42] . This ability is absent in our closest relatives, the great apes [1] , [4] . In addition, like human spoken language, birdsong involves patterned vocalizations that can be quite complex, with a set of rules that govern variable song element sequences known as “phonological syntax” [1] , [4] , [41] , [42] , [45] . Contrary to recent suggestions [46] , [47] , to date there is no evidence to suggest that birdsong patterns exhibit the hierarchical syntactic structure that characterizes human language [41] , [48] , [49] or any mapping to a level forming a language of thought as in humans. Avian vocal-learning species such as parrots are able to synchronize their behavior to variable rhythmic patterns [50] . Such rhythmic abilities may be involved in human prosodic processing, which is known to be an important factor in language acquisition [51] .

The Faculty of Language According to the “Strong Minimalist Thesis”

In the last few years, certain linguistic theories have arrived at a much more narrowly defined and precise phenotype characterizing human language syntax. In place of a complex rule system or accounts grounded on general notions of “culture” or “communication,” it appears that human language syntax can be defined in an extremely simple way that makes conventional evolutionary explanations much simpler. In this view, human language syntax can be characterized via a single operation that takes exactly two (syntactic) elements a and b and puts them together to form the set {a, b}. We call this basic operation “ merge ” [1] . The “Strong Minimalist Thesis” (SMT) [6] holds that merge along with a general cognitive requirement for computationally minimal or efficient search suffices to account for much of human language syntax. The SMT also requires two mappings: one to an internal conceptual interface for thought and a second to a sensory-motor interface that externalizes language as speech, sign, or other modality [1] . The basic operation itself is simple. Given merge , two items such as the and apples are assembled as the set { the, apples }. Crucially, merge can apply to the results of its own output so that a further application of merge to ate and { the, apples } yields the set { ate , { the, apples }}, in this way deriving the full range of characteristic hierarchical structure that distinguishes human language from all other known nonhuman cognitive systems.

As the text below and Figure 1 shows, merge also accounts for the characteristic appearance of displacement in human language—the apparent “movement” of phrases from one position to another. Displacement is not found in artificially constructed languages like computer programming languages and raises difficulties for parsing as well as communication. On the SMT account, however, displacement arises naturally and is to be expected, rather than exceptional, as seems true in every human language that has been examined carefully. Furthermore, hierarchical language structure is demonstrably present in humans, as shown, for instance, by online brain imaging experiments [7] , but absent in nonhuman species, e.g., chimpanzees taught sign language demonstrably lack this combinatorial ability [8] . Thus, before the appearance of merge , there was no faculty of language as such, because this requires merge along with the conceptual atoms of the lexicon. Absent this, there is no way to arrive at the essentially infinite number of syntactic language structures, e.g., “the brown cow,” “a black cat behind the mat” [9] – [11] , etc. This view leaves room for the possibility that some conceptual atoms were present antecedent to merge itself, though at present this remains entirely speculative. Even if true, there seems to be no evidence for an antecedent combinatorial and hierarchical syntax. Furthermore, merge itself is uniform in the contemporary human population as well as in the historical record, in contrast to human group differences such as the adult ability to digest lactose or skin pigmentation [12] . There is no doubt that a normal child from England raised in northern Alaska would readily learn Eskimo-Aleut, or vice versa; there have been no confirmed group differences in the ability of children to learn their first language, despite one or two marginal, indirect, and as yet unsubstantiated correlative indications [13] . This uniformity and stability points to the absence of major evolutionary change since the emergence of the language faculty. Taken together, these facts provide good evidence that merge was indeed the key evolutionary innovation for the language faculty.

thumbnail

  • PPT PowerPoint slide
  • PNG larger image
  • TIFF original image

Left: The circled structure Y, corresponding to what , the object of the verb eat , is a subset of the circled structure X, corresponding to boys eat what . Right: The free application of merge to X, Y in this case automatically leads to what occupying two syntactic positions, as required for proper semantic interpretation. The original what remains as the object of the verb so that it can serve as an argument to this predicate, and a copy of what , “displaced,” is now in the position of a quantificational operator so that the form can be interpreted as “for what x , boys eat x .” Typically, only the higher what is actually pronounced, as indicated by the line drawn through the lower what .

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pbio.1001934.g001

It is sometimes suggested that external motor sequences are “hierarchical” in this sense and so provide an antecedent platform for language [14] . However, as has been argued [15] , motor sequences resemble more the “sequence of letters in the alphabet than the sequences of words in a sentence” ( [15] , p. 221). (For expository purposes, we omit here several technical linguistic details about the labelling of these words; see [16] .) Along with the conceptual atoms of the lexicon, the SMT holds that merge , plus the internal interface mappings to the conceptual system, yields what has been called the “language of thought” [17] .

More narrowly, the SMT also suffices to automatically derive some of the most central properties of human language syntax. For example, one of the most distinctive properties of human language syntax is that of “displacement,” along with what is sometimes called “duality of semantic patterning.” For example, in the sentence “(Guess) what boys eat,” “what” takes on a dual role and is interpreted in two places: first, as a question “operator” at the front of the sentence, where it is pronounced; and second, as a variable that serves as the argument of the verb eat , the thing eaten, where it is not pronounced ( Figure 1 ). (There are marginal exceptions to the nonpronunciation of the second “what” that, when analyzed carefully, support the picture outlined here.) Given the free application of merge , we expect human languages to exhibit this phenomenon of displacement without any further stipulation. This is simply because operating freely, without any further constraints, merge derives this possibility. In our example “(Guess) what boys eat,” we assume that successive applications of merge as in our earlier example will first derive { boys , { eat, what }}—analogous to { boys , { eat, apples }}. Now we note that one can simply apply merge to the two syntactic objects { boys ,{ eat, what }} and { what }, in which { what } is a subcomponent (a subset) of the first syntactic object rather than some external set. This yields something like { what , { boys , { eat, what }}}, in this way marking out the two required operator and variable positions for what .

The Nature of Evolution

Evolutionary analysis might be brought to bear on language in two different ways. First, evolutionary considerations could be used to explain the mechanisms of human language. For instance, principles derived from studying the evolution of communication might be used to predict, or even explain, the structural organization of language. This approach is fraught with difficulties. Questions of evolution or function are fundamentally different from those relating to mechanism, so evolution can never “explain” mechanisms [18] . For a start, the evolution of a particular trait may have proceeded in different ways, such as via common descent, convergence, or exaptation, and it is not easy to establish which of these possibilities (or combination of them) is relevant [18] , [19] . More importantly, evolution by natural selection is not a causal factor of either cognitive or neural mechanisms [18] . Natural selection can be seen as one causal factor for the historical process of evolutionary change, but that is merely stating the essence of the theory of evolution. As we have argued, communication cannot be equated with language, so its evolution cannot inform the mechanisms of language syntax. However, evolutionary considerations—in particular, reconstructing the evolutionary history of relevant traits—might provide clues or hypotheses as to mechanisms, even though such hypotheses have frequently been shown to be false or misleading [18] . One such evolutionary clue is that, contrary to received wisdom, recent analyses suggest that significant genetic change may occur in human populations over the course of a few hundred years [19] . Such rapid change could also have occurred in the case of language, as we will argue below. In addition, as detailed in the next section, paleoanthropological evidence suggests that the appearance of symbolic thought, our most accurate proxy for language, was a recent evolutionary event. For instance, the first evidence of putatively symbolic artifacts dates back to only around 100,000 years ago, significantly after the appearance on the planet of anatomically distinctive Homo sapiens around 200,000 years ago [20] , [21] ,

The second, more traditional way of applying evolutionary analysis to language is to attempt to reconstruct its evolutionary history. Here, too, we are confronted with major explanatory obstacles. For starters, language appears to be unique to the species H. sapiens . That eliminates one of the cornerstones of evolutionary analysis, the comparative method, which generally relies on features that are shared by virtue of common descent ( Box 1 ) [1] , [4] , [18] . Alternatively, analysis can appeal to convergent evolution, in which similar features, such as birds' wings and bats' wings, arise independently to “solve” functionally analogous problems. Both situations help constrain and guide evolutionary explanation. Lacking both, as in the case of language, makes the explanatory search more difficult. In addition, evolutionary analysis of language is often plagued by popular, naïve, or antiquated conceptions of how evolution proceeds [19] , [22] . That is, evolution is often seen as necessarily a slow, incremental process that unfolds gradually over the eons. Such a view of evolutionary change is not consistent with current evidence and our current understanding, in which evolutionary change can be swift, operating within just a few generations, whether it be in relation to finches' beaks on the Galapagos, insect resistance to pesticides following WWII, or human development of lactose tolerance within dairy culture societies, to name a few cases out of many [19] , [22] – [24] .

Paleoanthropology

Language leaves no direct imprint in the fossil record, and the signals imparted by putative morphological proxies are highly mixed. Most of these involve speech production and detection, neither of which by itself is sufficient for inferring language (see Box 2 ). After all, while the anatomical potential to produce the frequencies used in modern speech may be necessary for the expression of language, it provides no proof that language itself was actually employed. What is more, it is not even necessary for language, as the visual and haptic externalization routes make clear. Moreover, even granting that speech is a requirement for language, it has been argued convincingly [25] , [26] that equal proportions of the horizontal and vertical portions of the vocal tract are necessary for producing speech. This conformation is uniquely seen in our own species Homo sapiens . In a similar vein, the aural ability of nonhuman primates like chimpanzees or extinct hominid species such as H. neanderthalensis to perceive the sound frequencies associated with speech [26] , [27] says nothing about the ability of these relatives to understand or produce language. Finally, neither the absolute size of the brain nor its external morphology as seen in endocasts has been shown to be relevant to the possession of language in an extinct hominid ( Figure 2 ) [28] . Recent research has determined that Neanderthals possessed the modern version of the FOXP2 gene [29] , malfunctions in which produce speech deficits in modern people [4] , [30] . However, FOXP2 cannot be regarded as “the” gene “for” language, since it is only one of many that have to be functioning properly to permit its normal expression.

thumbnail

Although after an initial flatlining this plot appears to show consistent enlargement of hominid brains over the last 2 million years, it is essential to note that these brain volumes are averaged across a number of independent lineages within the genus Homo and likely represent the preferential success of larger-brained species. From [20] . Image credit: Gisselle Garcia, artist (brain images) .

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pbio.1001934.g002

Box 2. The Infamous Hyoid Bone

A putative relationship between basicranial flexion, laryngeal descent, and the ability to produce sounds essential to speech was suggested [52] before any fossil hyoid bones, the sole hard-tissue components of the laryngeal apparatus, were known. It was speculated that fossil hyoids would indicate when speech, and by extension language, originated. A Neanderthal hyoid from Kebara in Israel eventually proved very similar to its H. sapiens homologue, prompting the declaration that speech capacity was fully developed in adult H. neanderthalensis [53] . This was soon contested on the grounds that the morphology of the hyoid is both subsidiary [25] and unrelated [26] to its still-controversial [36] position in the neck. A recent study [54] focuses on the biomechanics, internal architecture, and function of the Kebara fossil. The authors conclude that their results “add support for the proposition that the Kebara 2 Neanderthal engaged in speech” ( [54] , p. 6). However, they wisely add that the issue of Neanderthal language will be fully resolved only on the basis of fuller comparative material. While the peripheral ability to produce speech is undoubtedly a necessary condition for the expression of vocally externalized language, it is not a sufficient one, and hyoid morphology, like most other lines of evidence, is evidently no silver bullet for determining when human language originated.

In terms of historically calibrated records, this leaves us only with archaeology, the archive of ancient human behaviors—although we have once again to seek indirect proxies for language. To the extent that language is interdependent with symbolic thought [20] , the best proxies in this domain are objects that are explicitly symbolic in nature. Opinions have varied greatly as to what constitutes a symbolic object, but if one excludes stone and other Paleolithic implements from this category on the fairly firm grounds that they are pragmatic and that the techniques for making them can be passed along strictly by imitation [31] , we are left with objects from the African Middle Stone Age (MSA) such as pierced shell beads from various ∼100,000-year-old sites (e.g., [32] ) and the ∼80,000-year-old geometrically engraved plaques from South Africa's Blombos Cave [33] as the earliest undisputed symbolic objects. Such objects began to be made only substantially after the appearance, around 200,000 years ago, of anatomically recognizable H. sapiens , also in Africa [34] . To be sure, this inference from the symbolic record, like much else in paleontology, rests on evidence that is necessarily quite indirect. Nevertheless, the conclusion lines up with what is known from genomics.

Our species was born in a technologically archaic context [35] , and significantly, the tempo of change only began picking up after the point at which symbolic objects appeared. Evidently, a new potential for symbolic thought was born with our anatomically distinctive species, but it was only expressed after a necessary cultural stimulus had exerted itself. This stimulus was most plausibly the appearance of language in members of a species that demonstrably already possessed the peripheral vocal apparatus required to externalize it [20] , [22] . Then, within a remarkably short space of time, art was invented, cities were born, and people had reached the moon. By this reckoning, the language faculty is an extremely recent acquisition in our lineage, and it was acquired not in the context of slow, gradual modification of preexisting systems under natural selection but in a single, rapid, emergent event that built upon those prior systems but was not predicted by them. It may be relevant to note that the anatomical ability to express language through speech was acquired at a considerable cost, namely the not-insignificant risk of adults choking to death [25] , [36] , as simultaneous breathing and swallowing became impossible with the descent of the larynx. However, since this conformation was already in place before language had demonstrably been acquired (see Box 2 ), the ability to express language cannot by itself have been the countervailing advantage. Finally, there has been no detectable evolution of the language faculty since it emerged, with no known group differences. This is another signature of relatively recent and rapid origin. For reasons like these, the relatively sudden origin of language poses difficulties that may be called “Darwin's problem.”

The Minimalist Account of Language—Progress towards Resolving “Darwin's Problem”

The Strong Minimalist Thesis (SMT) [6] , as discussed above, greatly eases the explanatory burden for evolutionary analysis, since virtually all of the antecedent “machinery” for language is presumed to have been present long before the human species appeared. For instance, it appears that the ability to perceive “distinctive features” such as the difference between the sound b , as in bat , as opposed to p , as in pat , might be present in the mammalian lineage generally [37] , [38] . The same holds for audition. Both comprise part of the externalization system for language. Furthermore, the general constraint of efficient computation would also seem plausibly antecedent in the cognitive computation of ancestral species. The only thing lacking for language would be merge , some specific way to externalize the internal computations and, importantly, the “atomic conceptual elements” that we have identified with words. Without merge , there would be no way to assemble the arbitrarily large, hierarchically structured objects with their specific interpretations in the language of thought that distinguish human language from other animal cognitive systems—just as Darwin insisted: “A complex train of thought can be no more carried out without the use of words, whether spoken or silent, than a long calculation without the use of figures or algebra” ( [39] , p. 88). With merge , however, the basic properties of human language emerge. Evolutionary analysis can thus be focused on this quite narrowly defined phenotypic property, merge itself, as the chief bridge between the ancestral and modern states for language. Since this change is relatively minor, it accords with what we know about the apparent rapidity of language's emergence.

Conclusions

The Strong Minimalist Thesis that we have sketched here is consistent with a recent and rapid evolutionary emergence of language. Although this thesis is far from being established and contains many open questions, it offers an account that is compatible with the known empirical evolutionary evidence. Such an account also aligns with what we currently know about the relatively few genomic differences between our species and other ancestral Homo species—e.g., only about 100 coding gene differences between Homo sapiens and H. neanderthalensis , the majority of them in nonlanguage areas such as the olfactory and immune systems [40] . Furthermore, as far as we can tell from direct historical evidence, the capacity that emerged, namely the ability of any child to learn any human language, has remained frozen for 10,000 years or more. To be sure, such observations must be interpreted with great care and can remain only suggestive as long as we lack the knowledge to even crudely connect genomic changes to the relevant phenotypes. Even given these caveats, it appears that there has simply not been enough time for large-scale evolutionary changes, as indicated by the SMT. Clearly, such a novel computational system could have led to a large competitive advantage among the early H. sapiens who possessed it, particularly when linked to possibly preexisting perceptual and motor mechanisms.

  • View Article
  • Google Scholar
  • 6. Chomsky N (2000) Minimalist inquiries: The framework. In: Martin R, Michaels D, Uriagereka J, editors. Step by step: Essays on minimalist syntax in honor of Howard Lasnik. Cambridge (Massachusetts): MIT Press. pp. 89–155.
  • 9. Hurford J (2012) Language in the light of evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • 10. Jackendoff R (2003) Foundations of language: Brain, meaning, grammar, evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • 11. Bickerton D (1981) Roots of language. Ann Arbor (Michigan): Karoma Publishers.
  • 13. Ladd DR, Dediu D (2013) Genes and linguistic tone. In: Pashler H, editor. Encyclopedia of the mind. London: Sage Publications. pp. 372–373.
  • 17. Berwick R, Chomsky N (2011) The biolinguistic program: The current state of its development. In: Di Sciullo AM, Boeckx C, editors. The biolinguistic enterprise. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 19–41.
  • 21. Dubreuil B, Henshilwood CS (2013) Material culture and language. In: Lefebvre C, Comrie B, Cohen H, editors. New perspectives on the origin of language. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. pp. 147–170.
  • 22. Tattersall I (2012) Masters of the planet. The search for our human origins. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
  • 23. Thompson JH (2013) Relentless evolution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • 24. Nei M (2013) Mutation-driven evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • 28. DeSalle R, Tattersall I (2012) The brain: Big bangs, behaviors, and beliefs. New Haven (Connecticut): Yale University Press.
  • 36. Lieberman DE (2011) The evolution of the human head. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • 38. Hauser M, Fitch T (2003) What are the uniquely human components of the language faculty? In: Christiansen MH, Kirby S, editors. Language Evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 158–181.
  • 39. Darwin C (1871) The Descent of man, and selection in relation to sex. London: John Murray.
  • 42. Bolhuis JJ, Everaert M, editors (2013) Birdsong, speech, and language. Exploring the evolution of mind and brain. Cambridge (Massachusetts): MIT Press.
  • 49. Everaert M, Huybregts R (2013) The design principles of natural language. In: Bolhuis JJ, Everaert M, editors. Birdsong, speech, and language. Exploring the evolution of mind and brain. Cambridge (Massachusetts): MIT Press. pp. 1–26.

Evolutionary Development: A Universal Perspective

  • Conference paper
  • First Online: 26 June 2019
  • Cite this conference paper

learning is an evolutionary process essay

  • John M. Smart 5 , 6  

Part of the book series: Springer Proceedings in Complexity ((SPCOM))

1233 Accesses

2 Citations

This paper offers a general systems definition of the phrase “evolutionary development” and an introduction to its application to autopoetic (self-reproducing) complex systems, including the universe as a system. Evolutionary development, evo devo or ED, is a term that can be used by philosophers, scientists, historians, and others as a replacement for the more general term “evolution,” whenever a scholar thinks experimental, selectionist, stochastic, and contingent or “evolutionary” processes, and also convergent, statistically deterministic (probabilistically predictable), or “developmental” processes, including replication, may be simultaneously contributing to selection and adaptation in any complex system, including the universe as a system.

Like living systems, our universe broadly exhibits both contingent and deterministic components, in all historical epochs and at all levels of scale. It has a definite birth and it is inevitably senescing toward heat death. The idea that we live in an “evo devo universe,” one that has self-organized over past replications both to generate multilocal evolutionary variation (experimental diversity) and to convergently develop and pass to future generations selected aspects of its accumulated complexity (“intelligence”), is an obvious hypothesis. Yet today, few cosmologists or physicists, even among theorists of universal replication and the multiverse, have entertained the hypothesis that our universe may be both evolving and developing (engaging in both unpredictable experimentation and goal-driven, teleological, directional change and a replicative life cycle), as in living systems. Our models of universal replication, like Lee Smolin’s cosmological natural selection (CNS), do not yet use the concept of universal development, or refer to development literature.

I will argue that some variety of evo devo universe models must emerge in coming years, including models of CNS with Intelligence (CNSI), which explore the ways emergent intelligence can be expected to constrain and direct “natural” selection, as it does in living systems. Evo devo models are one of several early approaches to an Extended Evolutionary Synthesis (EES), one that explores adaptation in both living and nonliving replicators. They have much to offer as a general approach to adaptive complexity, and may be required to understand several important phenomena under current research, including galaxy formation, the origin of life, the fine-tuned universe hypothesis, possible Earthlike and life fecundity in astrobiology, convergent evolution, the future of artificial intelligence, and our own apparent history of unreasonably smooth and resilient acceleration of both total and “leading edge” adapted complexity and intelligence growth, even under frequent and occasionally extreme past catastrophic selection events. If they are to become better validated in living systems and in nonliving adaptive replicators, including stars, prebiotic chemistry, and the universe as a system, they will require both better simulation capacity and advances in a variety of theories, which I shall briefly review.

Support: No institutional support or grant was used for this work.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Adami, Chris (2016) What is Information? Phil. Trans. Royal Soc. A 374(2063)20150230.

Article   ADS   Google Scholar  

Adams, Fred C. (2008) Stars in Other Universes: Stellar structure with different fundamental constants, arXiv:0807.3697 [astro-ph].

Adams, A.M., Zenil, H., Davies, P.C.W., and Walker, S.I. (2016) Formal Definitions of Unbounded Evolution and Innovation Reveal Universal Mechanisms for Open-Ended Evolution in Dynamical Systems (preprint, ArXiv.org).

Google Scholar  

Aguirre, Anthony (2016) Why There is “Something” rather than “Nothing”, Interview by Lawrence Kuhn for Closer to Truth (YouTube, 4 min).

Arthur, Wallace (2000) The Origin of Animal Body Plans: A Study in Evolutionary Developmental Biology , Cambridge U. Press.

Aunger, Robert (2007a) Major transitions in ‘big’ history, Technological Forecasting and Social Change 74(8):1137–1163.

Article   Google Scholar  

——— (2007b) A rigorous periodization of ‘big’ history, Technological Forecasting and Social Change 74(8):1164–1178.

Barrow, John D. and Tipler, Frank (1986) The Anthropic Cosmological Principle , Oxford U. Press.

Barrow, John D. et al. (2008) Fitness of the Cosmos for Life: Biochemistry and Fine-Tuning , Cambridge U. Press.

Bejan, A. and Errera, M.R. (2017) Wealth inequality: The physics basis. J. Applied Physics 121(12):124903.

Bejan, A. and Zane, J.P. (2013) Design in Nature: How the Constructal Law Governs Evolution in Biology, Physics, Technology, and Social Organizations , Anchor.

Bhullar, B-A.S. (2017) Evolution: Catastrophe triggers diversification, Nature 542:304–305.

Bostrom, N. (2002) Anthropic Bias: Observation Selection Effects in Science and Philosophy , Routledge.

Bostrom, N. and Ćirković, M.M. (Eds.) (2008) Global Catastrophic Risks, 1st Edition , Oxford U. Press.

Bourgine, P. and Stewart, J. (2004) Autopoiesis and Cognition, Artificial Life 10: 327–345.

Bray, Dennis (2011) Wetware: A Computer in Every Living Cell , Yale U. Press.

Brin, David (1983) The ‘Great Silence’: the Controversy Concerning Extraterrestrial Intelligent Life, Q.J.R. Astr. Soc. 24:283–309.

Callebaut, Werner and Rasskin-Gutman, Diego (2005) Modularity: Understanding the Development and Evolution of Natural Complex Systems , MIT Press.

Calude, Cristian S. and Jürgensen, Helmut (2005) Is complexity a source of incompleteness? Advances in Applied Math 35(2005)1–15.

Article   MathSciNet   MATH   Google Scholar  

Carroll, Sean B. (2005) Endless Forms Most Beautiful: The New Science of Evo Devo , Norton.

Carroll, Sean M. (2016) The Big Picture: On the Origins of Life, Meaning, and the Universe Itself , Dutton.

Carter, Brandon (1974) Large Number Coincidences and the Anthropic Principle in Cosmology. IAU Symposium 63 , Reidel. pp. 291–298.

Chaitin, Gregory J. (1992) Information-Theoretic Incompleteness , World Scientific.

Chaisson, Eric (2001) Cosmic Evolution: The Rise of Complexity in Nature , Harvard U. Press.

Ćirković, M.M. (2009) Fermi’s Paradox – The Last Challenge for Copernicanism? Serbian Astronomical Journal 178, 1–20.

Ćirković, M.M., Sandberg, A., and Bostrom, N. (2010) Anthropic Shadow: Observation Selection Effects and Human Extinction Risks, Risk Analysis 30:1495–1506.

Clausius, Rudolf (1851) On the Moving Force of Heat, and the Laws regarding the Nature of Heat itself which are deducible therefrom, London, Edinburgh, and Dublin Philosophical Magazine and Journal of Science 4th. 2(VIII):1–21;102–119.

Comte, August (1844) Discours sur l’Esprit Positif [A General View of Positivism] , Paris.

Conway-Morris, Simon (1998) The Crucible of Creation: The Burgess Shale and the Rise of Animals , Oxford U. Press.

——— (2004) Life’s Solution: Inevitable Humans in a Lonely Universe , Cambridge U. Press.

——— (2015) The Runes of Evolution , Templeton Press.

Corning, Peter A. and Szathmáry, Eörs (2015) “Synergistic selection”: A Darwinian frame for the evolution of complexity. J. Theoretical Biology 371(2015)45–58.

Corning, Peter A. (2018) Synergistic Selection: How Cooperation has Shaped Evolution and the Rise of Humankind , World Scientific.

Crane, L. (1994) Possible Implications of the Quantum Theory of Gravity: An Introduction to the Meduso-Anthropic Principle (PDF). Foundations of Science Preprint 1994, no. Special Issue of the First Conference on the Evolution and Development of the Universe (EDU-2008).

Crutchfield, J.P. and van Nimwegen, E. (2002) The Evolutionary Unfolding of Complexity. In: Evolution as Computation , Landweber L.F., Winfree E. (Eds.), Natural Computing Series, Springer.

Dartnell, Lewis (2014) The Knowledge: How to Rebuild Our World from Scratch , Penguin Press.

Darwin, Charles (1859) (On) The Origin of Species (by Means of Natural Selection) , John Murray Press.

Davies, Paul (2010) The Eerie Silence: Renewing Our Search for Alien Intelligence , Houghton Mifflin Harcourt.

Dick, Steven J. (1996) The Biological Universe: The Extraterrestrial Life Debate and the Limits of Science , Cambridge U. Press.

Dryden, D.T.F., Thomson, A.R., and White, J.H. (2008) How much of protein sequence space has been explored by life on Earth?, J. R. Soc. Interface 5:953–956.

Einstein, Albert (1915) Die Feldgleichungen der Gravitation (The Field Equations of Gravitation), Sitzungsberichte der Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Berlin , 844–847.

Eldredge, N. and Gould, S.J. (1972) Punctuated equilibria: an alternative to phyletic gradualism, In: Models in Paleobiology , T.M. Schopf (ed.), Freeman & Cooper, pp. 82–115.

Ellis, G.F.R. (2015) Recognising Top-Down Causation, in A. Aguirre et al. (Eds.) Questioning the Foundations of Physics , Springer, pp. 17–44.

Ellis, G.F.R., Noble, D., and O’Connor, T. (2012) Top-down causation: an integrating theme within and across the sciences?, Interface Focus 2:1–3.

Fischler, Martin A. and Firschein, Oscar (1987) Intelligence: The Eye, the Brain, and the Computer , Addison-Wesley.

Flack, Jessica (2017) Life’s Information Hierarchy. In: From Matter to Life: Information and Causality , Walker, Sara I. et al. (Eds.), Cambridge U. Press.

Flores-Martinez, Claudio L. (2014) SETI in the light of cosmic convergent evolution. Acta Astronautica 104(1):341–349.

——— (2017) Introducing Biomimomics: Combining Biomimetics and Comparative Genomics for Constraining Organismal and Technological Complexity. In: Mangan M. et al. (Eds.) Biomimetic and Biohybrid Systems: Proceedings of Living Machines 2017 , Springer.

Forgan, D., Dayal, P., Cockell, C., and Libeskind, N. (2017) Evaluating galactic habitability using high-resolution cosmological simulations of galaxy formation, International Journal of Astrobiology 16:60–73.

Forward, Robert L. (1980) Dragon’s Egg , Del Rey.

Gardner, Andy and Conlon, Joseph P. (2013) Cosmological natural selection and the purpose of the universe, Complexity 18:48–56.

Article   ADS   MathSciNet   Google Scholar  

Gardner, James (2003) Biocosm: A New Scientific Theory of Evolution , Inner Ocean Publishing.

——— (2007) The Intelligent Universe: AI, ET, and the Emerging Mind of the Cosmos , New Page.

Georgiev, Georgi Y. et al. (2015) Mechanism of organization increase in complex systems, Complexity 21(2)18–28.

Gerhart, John C. and Kirschner, Marc W. (2005) The Plausibility of Life: Resolving Darwin’s Dilemma , Yale U. Press.

——— (2007) The theory of facilitated variation, PNAS 104 Suppl 1:8582–9.

Gilbert, S.F., Bosch, T.C.G., and Ledón-Rettig, C. (2015) Eco-Evo-Devo: Developmental symbiosis and developmental plasticity as evolutionary agents, Nature Reviews Genetics 16(10):611–622.

Gödel, Kurt (1931) On formally undecidable propositions of Principia. Mathematica and related systems (German), Monatshefte für Mathematik und Physik , 38(1)173–198.

Goodwin, Jay T. et al. (2014) Alternative Chemistries of Life: Empirical Approaches , NASA/NSF Workshop.

Gould, Stephen J. (1977) Ontogeny and Phylogeny , Harvard U. Press.

——— (2002) The Structure of Evolutionary Theory , Harvard U. Press.

Haken, Hermann (1984) The Science of Structure: Synergetics , Van Nostrand Reinhold.

Hall, Brian K. (Ed.) (2003) Environment, Development, and Evolution , MIT Press.

Harrison, Edward R. (1995) The Natural Selection of Universes Containing Intelligent Life (PDF). Quarterly Journal of the Royal Astronomical Society 36(3)193–203.

ADS   Google Scholar  

Henderson, Lawrence J. (1913) The Fitness of the Environment: An Inquiry into the Biological Significance of the Properties of Matter , Macmillan.

Heylighen, Francis (2007) The Global Superorganism: an evolutionary-cybernetic model of the emerging network society. Web published manuscript. Retrieved from: http://pespmc1.vub.ac.be/Papers/Superorganism.pdf

——— (2008) Accelerating socio-technological evolution: from ephemeralization and stigmergy to the Global Brain. In: Globalization as Evolutionary Process: Modeling Global Change , George Modelski, Tessaleno Devezas, and William R. Thompson (eds.), Routledge.

——— (2016) Stigmergy as a Universal Coordination Mechanism. Cognitive Systems Research 38:4–13.

Hoyle, Fred (1954) On nuclear reactions occurring in very hot stars: the synthesis of the elements from carbon to nickel, Astrophysics Journal Suppl. 1:121–146.

——— (1983) The Intelligent Universe: A New View of Creation and Evolution , Holt, Rinehart and Winston.

Jablonka, Eva and Lamb, Marion J. (1995) Epigenetic Inheritance and Evolution: the Lamarckian Dimension , Oxford U. Press.

——— (2005) Evolution in Four Dimensions: Genetic, Epigenetic, Behavioral, and Symbolic Variation in the History of Life , MIT Press.

Jablonski, D. (1986) Background and Mass Extinctions: The Alternation of Macroevolutionary Regimes, Science 231:129–133.

Jacobs, Lucia (2012) From Chemotaxis to the Cognitive Map: The function of olfaction. PNAS , 109(1):10693–10700.

Jantsch, Erich (1980) The Self-Organizing Universe: Scientific and Human Implications , Pergamon.

Johnson, Norman L. (2011) What a Developmental View Can Do for You. In: Thought Leader Forum , Michael J. Mouboussin (Ed.), Credit Suisse/First Boston.

Kaplan, Jonathan (2008) The end of the adaptive landscape metaphor? Biol Philos 23:625–638.

Kauffman, Stuart (1993) The Origins of Order: Self-Organization and Selection in Evolution , Oxford U. Press.

Koonin, Eugene V. (2007) The cosmological model of eternal inflation and the transition from chance to biological evolution in the history of life. Biology Direct 2:15–36.

Krumholz, M.R. and McKee, C.F. (2005) A general theory of turbulence-regulated star formation, from spirals to ultraluminous infrared galaxies. The Astrophysical Journal 630:250–268.

Kurzweil, Ray (1999) The Age of Spiritual Machines: When Computers Exceed Human Intelligence , Penguin.

——— (2005) The Singularity is Near , Penguin.

Laland, Kevin et al. (2015) The extended evolutionary synthesis: Its structure, assumptions and predictions, Proceedings of the Royal Society B282:20151019.

Lane, Nick (2016) The Vital Question , W.W. Norton.

Laplace, Pierre-Simon (1812) Theorie analytique des probabilites (A Philosophical Essay on Probabilities) , Translated from the fifth French edition of 1825 with Notes by the Translator, Andrew I. Dale, Springer-Verlag, 1995.

Lem, Stanislaw (1971) The New Cosmogony, In: A Perfect Vacuum (trans. by M. Kandel), Northwestern U. Press, 1999, pp. 197–227.

Leibniz, Gottfried (1686) The Discourse on Metaphysics (Fr: Discours de métaphysique) .

Leslie, John and Kuhn, Robert L. (2013) The Mystery of Existence: Why Is There Anything At All? , Wiley-Blackwell.

Levin, Simon A. (1998) Ecosystems and the Biosphere as Complex Adaptive Systems, Ecosystems 1:431–436.

Lewis, G.F. and Barnes, L.A. (2016) A Fortunate Universe: Life in a Finely Tuned Cosmos , Cambridge U. Press.

Lightman, Alan (2011) The Accidental Universe, Harpers , Dec 2011.

Lineweaver, Charles H., Fenner, Y., and Gibson, B.K. (2004) The Galactic Habitable Zone and the Age Distribution of Complex Life in the Milky Way, Science 303(5654):59–62.

Linde, Andrei D. (1992) Stochastic approach to tunneling and baby universe formation, Nuclear Physics B 372:421–442.

Lobkovsky, A.E. and Koonin, E.V. (2012) Replaying the tape of life: quantification of the predictability of evolution, Frontiers in Genetics 3:246–254.

Lorenz, Konrad (1977) Behind the Mirror: A Search for a Natural History of Human Knowledge , Harcourt, Brace, Jovanovich.

Losos, Johnathan B. (2017) Improbable Destinies: Fate, Chance, and the Future of Evolution , Riverhead Books.

Louis, A.A. (2016) Contingency, convergence and hyper-astronomical numbers in biological evolution, Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 58:107–116.

Lucas, J.R. (1961) Minds, Machines and Gödel. Philosophy 36:112–137.

Luhmann, Niklas (2002/2013) Introduction to Systems Theory , Polity Press.

Luisi, Pier L. (2003) Autopoiesis: a review and a reappraisal. Naturwissenschaften 90 49–59.

Malone, Michael S. (2012) The Guardian of All Things: The Epic Story of Human Memory , St. Martin’s Press.

Mariscal, Carlos (2016) Universal biology: assessing universality from a single example, In: The Impact of Discovering Life beyond Earth , Steven J. Dick (ed.), Cambridge U. Press.

Martin, Joseph D. (2013) Is the Contingentist/Inevitabilist Debate a Matter of Degrees? Philosophy of Science 80(5):919–930.

Maturana, H.R. and Varela, F.J. (1973/1980) Autopoiesis and Cognition: The Realization of The Living , D. Reidel.

——— (1987) The Tree of Knowledge: The Biological Roots of Human Understanding , Shambhala.

McGhee, George R. (2011) Convergent Evolution: Limited Forms Most Beautiful , MIT Press.

McLeish, T.C.B. (2015) Are there ergodic limits to evolution? Ergodic exploration of genome space and convergence, Interface Focus 5:41–53.

Meissner, Ulf-G. (2013) Life on earth – An accident? Chiral symmetry and the anthropic principle, Int. J. Mod. Phys. E 23.

Miller, James G. (1978) Living Systems , McGraw Hill.

Mingers, John (1995) Self-Producing Systems . Kluwer Academic/Plenum.

Moravec, Hans (1979) Today’s Computers, Intelligent Machines, and Our Future. Analog Science Fiction and Fact , Feb 1979.

Müller, Gerd B. and Newman, Stuart A. (Eds.) (2003) The Origination of Organismal Form: Beyond the Gene in Developmental and Evolutionary Biology , MIT Press.

Munitz, Milton K. (1987) Cosmic Understanding: Philosophy and Science of the Universe , Princeton U. Press.

Meyers, Robert A. (2009) Encyclopedia of Complexity and Systems Science , Springer.

Newton, Isaac (1687) The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy , Daniel Adee, 1846.

Noble, Denis (2017) Evolution viewed from physics, physiology and medicine. Interface Focus 7(5):20160159.

Noble, Raymond and Noble, Denis (2017) Was the Watchmaker Blind? Or Was She One-Eyed? Biology 6(4):47 (Special Issue: Biology in the Early 21st Century: Evolution Beyond Selection).

Odling-Smee, John et al. (2003) Niche Construction: The Neglected Process in Evolution , Princeton U. Press.

Ogura A., Kazuho, I., and Gojobori, T. (2004) Comparative analysis of gene expression for convergent evolution of camera eye between octopus and human. Genome Research 14:1555–1561.

O’Malley, M.A. and Powell, R. (2016) Major problems in evolutionary transitions: how a metabolic perspective can enrich our understanding of macroevolution, Biology and Philosophy 31:159–189.

Oparin, Alexander I. (1968) Genesis and Evolutionary Development of Life , Academic Press.

Orgogozo, V. (2015) Replaying the tape of life in the twenty-first century, Interface Focus 5:57–68.

Paley, William (1802) Natural Theology or Evidences of the Existence and Attributes of the Deity , John Morgan Press.

Pearce, T. (2012) Convergence and Parallelism in Evolution: A Neo-Gouldian Account, Brit. J. Phil. Sci. 63:429–448.

Article   MathSciNet   Google Scholar  

Piel, Gerard (1972) The Acceleration of History , Knopf.

Pigliucci, M (2007) Do we need an extended evolutionary synthesis?, Evolution 61:2743–2749.

Pigliucci, M. and Müller, G.B. (Eds.) (2010) Evolution: The Extended Synthesis , MIT Press.

Pinker, Steven (2010) The Better Angels of Our Nature: Why Violence Has Declined , Penguin.

Parker, Andrew (2003) In the Blink of an Eye , Basic Books.

Powell, R. (2012) Convergent evolution and the limits of natural selection, Euro. J. Phil. Sci. 2:355–373.

Powell, R. and Mariscal, C. (2015) Convergent evolution as natural experiment: the tape of life reconsidered, Interface Focus 5:40–53.

Pohorille, Andrew (2012) Processes that Drove the Transition from Chemistry to Biology: Concepts and Evidence. Origins of Life 42(5)429–432.

Poundstone, William (1985) The Recursive Universe: Cosmic Complexity and the Limits of Scientific Knowledge, William Morrow & Co.

Price, Michael (2017) Entropy and selection: Life as an adaptation for universe replication (PDF). Complexity , Article ID 4745379, 4 pages, 2017. doi: https://doi.org/10.1155/2017/4745379 .

Pross, Addy (2014) What is Life? How Chemistry Becomes Biology , Oxford U. Press.

Raff, Rudolf (1996) The Shape of Life: Genes, Development, and the Evolution of Animal Form , U. of Chicago Press.

Ray, Georgia (2017) Evolutionary Innovation as a Global Catastrophic Risk, Presentation at EA Global 2017, San Francisco, CA.

Rees, Martin (1999) Just Six Numbers: The Deep Forces that Shape Our Universe , Basic Books.

——— (2001) Our Cosmic Habitat , Princeton U. Press.

——— (2015) Post-human evolution on Earth and beyond. Presented at Exploring Exoplanets: The Search for Extraterrestrial Life and Post Biological Intelligence , John Templeton Foundation conference.

Reid, Robert G.B. (2007) Biological Emergences: Evolution by Natural Experiment , MIT Press.

Rosenstein, Melissa G. et al. (2012) Risk of Stillbirth and Infant Death Stratified by Gestational Age, Obstet Gynecol 120(1):76–82.

Russell, Cathy M. (2006) Retrieved from Epicofevolution.com/biological-evolution , 27 Mar 2017.

Russell, D. A. and Séguin, R. (1982) Reconstructions of the small Cretaceous theropod Stenonychosaurus inequalis and a hypothetical dinosauroid. Ottawa: National Museums of Canada, National Museum of Natural Sciences.

Sagan, Carl (1977) The Dragons of Eden: Speculations on the Evolution of Human Intelligence , Random House.

——— (1980) Cosmos , Random House.

Salthe, Stanley M. (1985) Evolving Hierarchical Systems , Columbia U. Press.

——— (1993) Development and Evolution: Complexity and Change in Biology , MIT Press.

——— (2010) Development (and evolution) of the universe. In: The Evolution and Development of the Universe , C. Vidal (ed.), Foundations of Science 15:357–367.

——— (2012) Hierarchical structures, Axiomathes 22:355–383.

Sanderson, M. and Hufford, L. (Eds.) (1996) Homoplasy: The Recurrence of Similarity in Evolution , Academic Press.

Schlosser, G. and Wagner, G.P. (Eds.) (2004) Modularity in Development and Evolution , U. of Chicago Press.

Shapiro, James A. (2011) Evolution: A View From the 21st Century , FT Press Science.

Signor, P.W. and Lipps, J.H. (1982) Sampling bias, gradual extinction patterns, and catastrophes in the fossil record, In: Geological implications of impacts of large asteroids and comets on the Earth , L.T. Silver and P.H. Schultz (Eds.), Geological Society of America Special Publication, 190:291–296.

Smart, John M. (2000) The developmental singularity hypothesis (DSH), AccelerationWatch.com . Retrieved from: Accelerationwatch.com/developmentalsinghypothesis.html , 29 Jan 2018.

——— (2002) Understanding STEM compression in universal change, AccelerationWatch.com. Retrieved from: Accelerationwatch.com/mest.html , 29 Jan 2018.

——— (2008) Evo Devo Universe? A Framework for Speculations on Cosmic Culture. In: Cosmos and Culture: Cultural Evolution in a Cosmic Context , Steven J. Dick, Mark L. Lupisella (Eds.), NASA Press.

——— (2012) The transcension hypothesis: Sufficiently advanced civilizations invariably leave our universe, and implications for METI and SETI, Acta Astronautica 78:55–68.

——— (2015) Humanity rising: Why evolutionary developmentalism will inherit the future, World Future Review 7(2–3):116–130.

——— (2016a) Portals (funnels, bottlenecks) and convergent evolution. In: The Foresight Guide . Retrieved from Foresightguide.com/portals-funnels-bottlenecks-and-convergent-evolution , 20 Jan 2018.

——— (2016b) The great race to inner space. In: The Foresight Guide . Retrieved from: Foresightguide.com/the-great-race-to-inner-space-our-surprising-future/ , 28 Mar 2017.

——— (2017a) The VCRIS model of natural selection. In: The Foresight Guide . Retrieved from: Foresightguide.com/the-vcris-model-of-natural-selection-evolutionary-development-of-adaptive-complexity , 6 Jun 2018.

——— (2017b) Five goals of complex systems. In: The Foresight Guide . Retrieved from: Foresightguide.com/five-goals-of-complex-systems , 30 Dec 2017.

——— (2018) Catalytic catastrophes: Advancing the five goals. In: The Foresight Guide . Retrieved from: Foresightguide.com/catalytic-catastrophes-how-right-sized-catastrophes-advance-the-five-goals/ , 20 Jan 2018.

Smith, Eric and Morowitz, Harold J. (2004) Universality in intermediary metabolism, Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. 101:13168–13173.

——— (2016) The Origin and Nature of Life on Earth , Cambridge U. Press.

Smolin, Lee (1992) Did the Universe Evolve? Classical and Quantum Gravity 9:173–191.

——— (1997) The Life of the Cosmos , Oxford U. Press.

——— (2004) Cosmological natural selection as the explanation for the complexity of the universe. Physica A 340:705–713.

——— (2006) The status of cosmological natural selection. arXiv:hep-th/0612185v1.

——— (2012) Scientific Approaches to the Fine-Tuning Problem, The Nature of Reality , Nova.

Spencer, Herbert (1864) Illustrations of Universal Progress: A Series of Discussions , D. Appleton.

Steele, Edward J. (1981) Somatic Selection and Adaptive Evolution: On the Inheritance of Acquired Characters, 2nd Ed. , U. of Chicago Press.

——— (1998) Lamarck’s Signature: How retrogenes are changing the natural selection paradigm , Perseus.

Stenger, Victor J. (2011) The Fallacy of Fine-Tuning: Why the Universe is Not Designed for Us , Prometheus.

Susskind, Leonard (2006) The Cosmic Landscape , Back Bay.

Swenson, Rod (1992) “Galileo, Babel, and Autopoiesis (It’s Turtles All The Way Down)”. Int. J. General Systems 21 (2): 267–269.

Taleb, Nicholas (2012) Antifragile: Things That Gain from Disorder , Random House.

Teilhard de Chardin, Pierre (1955) The Phenomenon of Man , Harper & Row.

Turchin, Valentin (1977) The Phenomenon of Science , Columbia U. Press.

Turner, D.D. (2011) Gould’s replay revisited, Biology and Philosophy 26:65–79.

Tyson, Neal D. (2006) The Perimeter of Ignorance, Presentation at: Beyond Belief Conference , Nov 5–7, 2006, YouTube (41 mins).

Vaas, Rüdiger (1998) Is there a Darwinian evolution of the cosmos? In: Proceedings of the MicroCosmos-MacroCosmos Conference , Aachen.

Varela F.J., Maturana, H.R., and Uribe, R. (1974) Autopoiesis: the organization of living systems, its characterization and a model, Biosystems 5(4):187–196.

Verhulst, Jos (2003) Discovering Evolutionary Principles through Comparative Morphology , Adonis Press.

Vermeij, Geerat J. (1987) Evolution and Escalation , Princeton U. Press.

——— (2006) Historical contingency and the purported uniqueness of evolutionary innovations, PNAS 103:1804–1809.

——— (2009) Nature: an economic history , Princeton U. Press.

Vidal, Clement (2008a) The future of scientific simulations: from artificial life to artificial cosmogenesis (PDF). In: Death and Anti-Death 6: Thirty Years After Kurt Gödel (1906–1978) .

——— (2010) Computational and biological analogies for understanding fine-tuned parameters in physics (PDF). Foundations of Science 15(4):375–393.

——— (2016) Stellivore Extraterrestrials? Binary Stars as Living Systems (PDF). Acta Astronautica 128:251–56.

Vilenkin, Alexander (2006) Many Worlds In One: The Search for Other Universes , Hill and Wang.

Volk, Tyler (2003) Gaia’s Body: Toward a Physiology of Earth , MIT Press.

——— (2017) Quarks to Culture: How We Came to Be , Columbia U. Press.

Wagner, Gunther (2003) Hox cluster duplications and the opportunity for evolutionary novelties, PNAS 100(25):14603–14606.

Wagman and Stephens (2004) Surprising ‘ultra-conserved’ regions discovered in human genome. UCSC Currents .

Walker, Sara I. et al. (Eds.) (2017) From Matter to Life: Information and Causality , Cambridge U. Press.

Webb, Stephen (2015) Where is Everybody? Seventy-Five Solutions to the Fermi Paradox and the Problem of Extraterrestrial Life , Springer.

Weinberg, Steven (2007) “Living in the Multiverse”, In: Universe or Multiverse? B. Carr (ed.), Cambridge U. Press.

West, Geoffrey (2017) Scale: The Universal Laws of Growth, Innovation, Sustainability, and the Pace of Life in Organisms, Cities, Economies, and Companies , Penguin.

West-Eberhard, Mary Jane (2003) Developmental Plasticity and Evolution , Oxford U. Press.

Wheeler, John A. (1977) Genesis and observership, In: Foundational Problems in the Special Sciences , R. E. Butts and J. Hintikka, (Eds.), D. Reidel, pp. 3–33.

——— (1988) World as system self-synthesized by quantum networking, IBM Journal of Research and Development 32:4–15.

Wigner, Eugene (1960) The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences. Comm. on Pure and Applied Math. , 13(1):1–14.

Article   ADS   MATH   Google Scholar  

Wikipedia (2008b), and Smart, John M. and Vidal, Clement (2008–2017). Cosmological natural selection (fecund universes). EvoDevoUniverse.com wiki.

Wikipedia (2012), and Smart John M. and Chattergee, Atanu (2012–2017). List of examples of convergent evolution. EvoDevoUniverse.com wiki.

Wilkins, Adam S. (2001) The Evolution of Developmental Pathways , Sinauer Associates.

Wright, Sewall (1932) The roles of mutation, inbreeding, crossbreeding, and selection in evolution. Proceedings of the Sixth International Congress on Genetics . pp. 355–366.

Yi, Hong et al. (2010) Gene expression atlas for human embryogenesis. FASEB Journal 24(9):3341–3350.

Zimmer, Carl (2015) A Planet of Viruses, 2nd Edition , U. Chicago Press.

Download references

Acknowledgments

The author thanks Evo Devo Universe co-directors Clement Vidal, Georgi Yordanov Georgiev, Michael Price, and Claudio Flores-Martinez for helpful critiques. Special thanks go to EDU member Milan Ćirković who offered extensive constructive feedback on the earliest version of this paper. Thanks also to Anthony Aguirre, John Leslie, Denis Noble, Rüdiger Vaas and Tyler Volk for key insights, and to Carlos Gershenson and the CCS committee for approving our satellite on Evolution, Development, and Complexity at CCS2017, where these and other ideas were discussed.

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

Acceleration Studies Foundation, Los Gatos, CA, USA

John M. Smart

Naval Postgraduate School, Monterey, CA, USA

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John M. Smart .

Editor information

Editors and affiliations.

Department of Physics, Worcester Polytechnic Institute, Worcester, MA, USA

Georgi Yordanov Georgiev

Department of Biology, Institute of Zoology, Molecular Evolutionary Biology, University of Hamburg, Hamburg, Germany

Claudio L. Flores Martinez

Department of Life Sciences, Centre for Culture and Evolution, Brunel University London, Uxbridge, UK

Michael E. Price

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this paper

Cite this paper.

Smart, J.M. (2019). Evolutionary Development: A Universal Perspective. In: Georgiev, G., Smart, J., Flores Martinez, C., Price, M. (eds) Evolution, Development and Complexity. Springer Proceedings in Complexity. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-00075-2_2

Download citation

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-00075-2_2

Published : 26 June 2019

Publisher Name : Springer, Cham

Print ISBN : 978-3-030-00074-5

Online ISBN : 978-3-030-00075-2

eBook Packages : Physics and Astronomy Physics and Astronomy (R0)

Share this paper

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

  • Publish with us

Policies and ethics

  • Find a journal
  • Track your research

SEP home page

  • Table of Contents
  • Random Entry
  • Chronological
  • Editorial Information
  • About the SEP
  • Editorial Board
  • How to Cite the SEP
  • Special Characters
  • Advanced Tools
  • Support the SEP
  • PDFs for SEP Friends
  • Make a Donation
  • SEPIA for Libraries
  • Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic tools.

  • Friends PDF Preview
  • Author and Citation Info
  • Back to Top

Morality and Evolutionary Biology

An article in The Economist (21 February 2008, “Moral thinking”), sporting the provocative subtitle “Biology Invades a Field Philosophers Thought was Safely Theirs”, begins with the following rumination:

Whence morality? That is a question which has troubled philosophers since their subject was invented. Two and a half millennia of debate have, however, failed to produce a satisfactory answer. So now it is time for someone else to have a go. [ 1 ]

And the article closes with the line “Perhaps [biologists] can eventually do what philosophers have never managed, and explain moral behavior in an intellectually satisfying way.” These passages epitomize a growing theme in the popular and scientific media, echoing claims made forty years ago with the emergence of sociobiology , when E.O. Wilson suggested that “the time has come for ethics to be removed temporarily from the hands of the philosophers and biologicized” (Wilson 1975, 562). For their part, moral philosophers will hasten to point out that they are not primarily in the business of “explaining moral behavior” in the sense of causally explaining the origins of our capacity for moral judgment or of various associated emotional and behavioral dispositions. If a moral philosopher asks “whence morality,” she is more likely to be concerned with the justification of moral principles or the source and nature of obligation. Still, there are important potential connections between the scientific explanatory issues and philosophical ones, opening the way for profitable interdisciplinary inquiry.

Section 1 provides an overview of the issues and a sketch of the connections between them, highlighting important distinctions we will need throughout. Sections 2, 3 and 4 then go on to explore critically the three main branches of inquiry at the intersection of morality and evolutionary biology: Descriptive Evolutionary Ethics, Prescriptive Evolutionary Ethics, and Evolutionary Metaethics.

1.1 Three Kinds of Appeal to Evolution in Evolutionary Ethics

1.2 the empirical and normative senses of ‘morality’, 2.1 levels and types of explanation: some possibilities, 2.2 biological and psychological altruism, 2.3 explaining the origins of morality: from psychological altruism to the evolution of normative guidance, 2.4 autonomous moral reflection and the explanation of reasoned moral judgment and behavior, 2.5 the challenge to the autonomous reflection model: post hoc rationalization of emotionally caused judgment, 3.1 spencer, 3.2 biology and the autonomy of ethics, 3.3 corrective uses of evolutionary biology in normative ethics, 3.4 the question of moral progress, 4.1 general evolutionary debunking arguments, 4.2 selective evolutionary debunking arguments, 4.3 evolutionary biology and expressivism, other internet resources, related entries, 1. overview: basic issues, questions, and distinctions.

Very little in the study of human life has been left untouched by developments in evolutionary biology, and inquiry into the nature of morality is no exception. With the recognition that we, like all other living things, belong to a species that has evolved through natural selection comes the acknowledgement that evolutionary processes have likewise shaped us deeply. How deeply?

Evolutionary explanations are commonplace when it comes to questions about our physiological nature—why we have opposable thumbs, say, or a bipedal posture. But even a brief look at other animals affords countless examples of adaptive psychological and behavioral traits as well—appetites for food or sex, fear responses, patterns of aggression, parental care and bonding, or patterns of cooperation and retribution; and these traits are likewise often best explained as biological adaptations, i.e., traits that evolved through natural selection due to their adaptive effects. (We will go through a striking example involving cooperative behavior in section 2.2.) This raises the question: to what extent might human psychological and behavioral traits similarly reflect our own evolutionary heritage?

When it comes to morality, the most basic issue concerns our capacity for normative guidance : our ability to be motivated by norms of behavior and feeling through judgments about how people ought to act and respond in various circumstances (Joyce 2006, Kitcher 2006a,b, 2011, and Machery and Mallon 2010). Is this human capacity a biological adaptation, having perhaps conferred a selective advantage on our hominin ancestors by enhancing social cohesion and cooperation? (‘Hominin’ refers, as did ‘hominid’ until very recently, to Homo sapiens together with fossil species of ape to which Homo sapiens are more closely related than we are to chimpanzees; these include the Australopithecines, extinct species of Homo , etc., making up the tribe Hominini within the sub-family Homininae.)

If so, then it would be part of evolved human nature to employ moral judgment in governing human behavior, rather than a mere “cultural veneer” artificially imposed on an amoral human nature (de Waal 2006). This would be a significant result, and it is only the beginning of the intriguing questions that arise at the intersection of morality and evolutionary biology. Researchers are also interested in the possibility of more specific forms of evolutionary influence. Are there, for example, emotional adaptations that influence the very content of moral judgments and behavior, even today?

For example, many of us believe that among our various moral duties, we have special and stringent duties toward family members. Might this ‘moral intuition’ be attributable, at least in part, to an evolved tendency to favor members of one’s kin group over others, analogous to similar traits in other animals? Even where moral beliefs are heavily shaped by culture, there might be such evolutionary influences in the background: evolved psychological traits may have contributed to the shaping of cultural practices themselves, influencing, for example, the development of “family first” cultural norms that inform our judgments. Similarly with a tendency more generally to favor members of one’s own group (however defined) over outsiders.

The above sorts of questions, which are receiving growing attention in the sciences, all pertain to morality understood as a set of empirical phenomena to be explained : it is an empirical fact about human beings that we make moral judgments, have certain feelings and behave in certain ways, and it is natural for the sciences to seek causal explanations for such phenomena. At the same time, however, it is a very complex matter—and one often neglected outside of philosophy—how such empirical, explanatory projects are related to the very different sets of questions and projects pursued by philosophers when they inquire into the nature and source of morality.

Moral philosophers tend to focus on questions about the justification of moral claims, the existence and grounds of moral truths, and what morality requires of us. These are very different from the empirical questions pursued in the sciences, but how we answer each set of questions may have implications for how we should answer the other. As we will see, though the two sets of issues are distinct, the scientific explanatory projects raise potential challenges for certain philosophical views, and at the same time attention to philosophical issues raises doubts about some of the explanatory claims made in the name of science, which often rely on controversial philosophical assumptions. Progress in this area will not be made either by doing moral philosophy in isolation from the sciences or by taking morality out of the hands of philosophers and looking to scientific inquiry in isolation. More promising would be a careful examination of the ways in which the scientific and philosophical projects inform each other.

Talk of ‘evolutionary ethics’ may suggest a well-defined field of inquiry, but in practice it can refer to any or all of the following:

  • Descriptive Evolutionary Ethics : appeals to evolutionary theory in the scientific explanation of the origins of certain human capacities, tendencies, or patterns of thought, feeling and behavior. For example: the appeal to natural selection pressures in the distant past to explain the evolution of a capacity for normative guidance, or more specifically the origins of our sense of fairness or our resentment of cheaters. (See section 2.)
  • Prescriptive Evolutionary Ethics : appeals to evolutionary theory in justifying or undermining certain normative ethical claims or theories—for example, to justify free market capitalism or male-dominant social structures, or to undermine the claim that human beings have a special dignity that non-human animals lack. (See section 3.)
  • Evolutionary Metaethics : appeals to evolutionary theory in supporting or undermining various metaethical theories (i.e., theories about moral discourse and its subject matter)—for example, to support a non-cognitivist account of the semantics of moral judgment (the idea that moral judgments do not purport to represent moral facts but instead just express emotions, attitudes or commitments), or to undermine the claim that there are objective moral values, or to cast doubt on whether we could have justified beliefs about such values. (See section 4.)

All three types of project have broadly to do with how neo-Darwinian evolutionary theory might bear on our understanding of ethics or morality . The driving questions, concerns, methodologies and implications, however, differ greatly among these three lines of inquiry.

Importantly, there are no simple or straightforward moves from the scientific projects in A to the philosophical projects in B or C. Arguments for or against such moves require difficult philosophical work. Moreover, philosophical issues relevant to C can have an important bearing on at least some of the scientific explanatory projects in A. This puts important constraints on how much can confidently be said in favor of such scientific explanations given ongoing controversy over the philosophical issues.

It is, for example, a matter of live debate in contemporary metaethics whether there are knowable moral truths —correct answers to at least some questions about what is morally good or bad, right or wrong. If there are, as many philosophers (and non-philosophers) believe, then this will likely make a difference to the explanation of at least some of our moral beliefs and behaviors. Our belief in equal human dignity, for example, along with derivative beliefs about the wrongness of slavery or rape, might be sufficiently explained by our having grasped the moral truth that human beings have such dignity and so should not be treated as “mere means” (see section 2.4). Similarly, the belief that we have moral obligations to mitigate suffering even among distant strangers might be explained at least in part by our having grasped the moral fact that pointless suffering is intrinsically bad and that this gives us good reason to mitigate it where we can.

If this is so, then scientists will be overreaching if they claim that “causal explanations of brain activity and evolution…already cover most known facts about behavior we term ‘moral’” (Wilson 1998, 54). Instead, a significant amount of moral judgment and behavior may be the result of gaining moral knowledge, rather than just reflecting the causal conditioning of evolution. This might apply even to universally held moral beliefs or distinctions, which are often cited as evidence of an evolved “universal moral grammar” (Mikhail 2011). For example, people everywhere and from a very young age distinguish between violations of merely conventional norms and violations of norms involving harm , and they are strongly disposed to respond to suffering with concern (Nichols 2004). But even if this partly reflects evolved psychological mechanisms or ‘modules’ governing social sentiments and responses, much of it may also be the result of human intelligence grasping (under varying cultural conditions) genuine morally relevant distinctions or facts—such as the difference between the normative force that attends harm and that which attends mere violations of convention.

We will look in more detail later at this and other possibilities for explaining moral judgment and behavior. The point so far is just that there are plausible philosophical accounts of at least some moral judgment and behavior that appeal to independent exercises of judgment—perhaps in grasping moral truths, or perhaps just in forming reflective commitments—rather than to causal conditioning by evolutionary factors. There is a danger, then, of begging central questions if we draw general conclusions about “the” explanation of “our” moral thought and behavior based on scientific considerations—as is common in discussions of scientific work in this area. We may instead need a plurality of explanatory models. The best explanation for deeply reflective moral judgments may look quite different from the explanation for unreflective psychological dispositions we share with other primates, and there may be mixed explanations for much that lies in between.

As a final preliminary point, it is useful to clear up one persistent source of confusion in discussions of morality and evolution by distinguishing between two very different senses of ‘morality’ and describing more explicitly the different sets of questions associated with them.

  • The Empirical Sense of ‘Morality’

People coming from a scientific perspective, who are interested in descriptive evolutionary ethics, speak of morality as something to be explained scientifically—as in familiar talk of “how morality evolved”. Here ‘morality’ refers, as noted earlier, to a certain set of empirical phenomena , such as the observed capacity of human beings to make normative judgments, or the tendency to have certain sentiments such as sympathy or guilt or blame, or certain ‘intuitions’ about fairness or violence. Just as we can inquire into the origins and functions of other traits, such as human linguistic capacities, we can inquire into the origins and functions of the various psychological capacities and tendencies associated with ‘morality’.

The sense of ‘morality’ in the above questions may be called the empirical sense of the term, and it is in this sense that scientists speak of “the evolution of morality,” using such tools as comparative genomics and primate studies to shed light on it (Rosenberg 2006; de Waal 1996 and 2006). Such explanatory projects will be discussed in section 2.

  • The Normative Sense of ‘Morality’

In contrast to the above, there is a very different use of the term ‘morality’ in what may be called the normative sense . Consider the question: “Does morality require that we make substantial sacrifices to help distant strangers?” Such a question arises from the deliberative standpoint as we seek to determine how we ought to live, and it is a normative rather than an empirical question. We are not here asking an anthropological question about some actual moral code—even that of our own society—but a normative question that might lead us to a new moral code. When we use ‘morality’ in the normative sense, it is meant to refer to however it is we ought to live , i.e., to a set of norms that ought to be adopted and followed . [ 2 ]

Philosophers employ this normative sense of ‘morality’ or ‘moral’ in posing a variety of both normative and metaethical questions: What does morality require of us? Does morality have a purely consequentialist structure, as utilitarians claim? What kind of meaning do claims about morality in the normative sense have? Are there moral truths—i.e., truths about morality in the normative sense—and if so, what are they grounded in and how can we come to know them? Is morality culturally relative or at least partly universal? (Note that this is not the same as the anthropological question whether or to what extent morality in the empirical sense varies from culture to culture.)

While morality in the normative sense is not an empirical phenomenon to be explained, there are still important questions to ask about how evolutionary theory may bear on it. Can we look to our evolutionary background for moral guidance, gaining insight into the content of morality in the normative sense (as claimed by proponents of prescriptive evolutionary ethics)? (Section 3) Does evolutionary theory shed light on metaethics, helping to resolve questions about the existence and nature of morality in the normative sense (as claimed by proponents of evolutionary metaethics)? Does it, for example, lend support to nihilism (the idea that there is really no such thing as morality in the normative sense ) or to skepticism (the idea that even if there are truths about morality in the normative sense we cannot know them, or at least could not know them if they were objective truths)? (Section 4)

Having distinguished various issues and questions, we may turn now to consider first the scientific explanatory projects concerning morality in the empirical sense.

2. Descriptive Evolutionary Ethics: Explaining Morality in the Empirical Sense

Evolutionary explanations for morality in the empirical sense are offered at different levels, and this makes for very different explanatory projects with different implications. Some typical explananda in accounts of “the evolution of morality” are:

  • The general capacity for normative judgment and guidance, and the tendency to exercise this capacity in social life;
  • The capacity for certain sentiments and the ability to detect them in others;
  • The tendency to experience and to be motivated by certain sentiments in certain types of situation;
  • The tendency to make certain particular kinds of moral judgment or inference, or to have certain characteristic moral intuitions (i.e., a ‘moral sense’);
  • The tendency to exhibit certain particular types of behavior in certain types of situation (as a result of D);
  • The tendency of societies to exhibit certain particular systems of norms or types of practice (due to D and E).

It is uncontroversial that there will be evolutionary explanations of some sort for the very general capacities and tendencies in A and B: we are evolved creatures, and our psychological capacities, like other complex capacities, are outcomes of evolutionary processes. But this does not by itself settle whether these capacities and tendencies are themselves adaptations , having evolved through natural selection because of their adaptive effects. That is the most common view (further explored below), but there are alternatives.

It is possible, for example, that our capacity to make moral judgments is a spin-off (side-effect or by-product) of our non-moral intellectual capacities, which latter are adaptations. [ 3 ] On this view, we tend to make moral judgments because we are intellectual and reflective creatures, not because natural selection has specifically given us this moral capacity and tendency as an adaptation; the role of natural selection would be indirect, supplying more general capacities as adaptations, from which specifically moral tendencies spring independently (Ayala 2006; Prinz 2008, Machery and Mallon 2010).

The deeper point, however, is that whichever position one takes on the role of natural selection in the emergence of generic capacities for moral judgment, this does not settle how best to account for other, more specific tendencies, such as C-F. In particular:

  • Even if (1) our capacity and tendency to make moral judgments is an adaptation that evolved through natural selection, it remains possible that (2) the content of particular moral judgments is derived autonomously , i.e., free from causal shaping by particular elements in our evolutionary background—in roughly the way that the contents of our beliefs in physics or philosophy seem to be (see section 2.4 below).
  • Alternatively, even if (1*) our capacity and tendency to make moral judgments is not itself an adaptation, it remains possible that (2*) the content of particular moral judgments is deeply shaped by evolved emotional dispositions that have affected the content of moral judgments since human beings began making them. Such emotional adaptations may thus have influenced cultural norms throughout history and may continue to influence our moral judgments, and hence our behavior, today.

And of course there are other possibilities: 1 might be combined with 2*, or 1* might be combined with 2, and both 2 and 2* could also be weakened to apply only to some judgments, while others are explained in other ways, as suggested earlier. There are, then, many possible stories to be told about the origins of our moral judgments and behavior.

Since our concern is with morality , the crucial issue to begin with is the origins of moral judgment : for morality has not merely to do with certain emotions and behaviors (such as sympathy and altruism) as such, but with the exercise of moral judgment about how one ought to behave in various social circumstances (Joyce 2006, ch. 2; Korsgaard 2006; Kitcher 2006c, 2011; Machery and Mallon 2010). Certain emotions and behaviors are then relevant too insofar as they relate to the exercise of such judgment, but in the absence of moral judgment they seem only to belong to proto-morality.

Still, many discussions employ a looser notion of ‘morality’ that refers simply to certain kinds of socially positive emotion or behavior, such as psychological altruism (defined below). Since accounts of the origins of moral judgment rely on these ideas as well, and these emotions or behavioral dispositions are also often appealed to as causal influences on the content of moral judgment, it is worth starting with a look at the issue of psychological altruism, distinguishing it from merely biological altruism.

Many discussions of morality and evolutionary biology focus largely on the issue of altruistic feeling and behavior. This can be confusing because in addition to psychological altruism there is also biological altruism , which is found in many species. (See Kitcher 2011, part I, for a comprehensive discussion.) Psychological altruism involves caring about others’ welfare and deliberately benefiting them for their own sake , with no restriction on the type of benefit involved. By contrast, biological altruism has nothing essentially to do with intentions or motives, and it pertains only to ‘benefits’ to others that increase their reproductive fitness (boosting their genetic contribution to future generations).

Though psychological altruism is different from biological altruism, there are a variety of possible explanations of the evolution of psychological altruism that appeal to the same factors that explain the origins of biological altruism, namely:

  • Kin selection or ‘inclusive fitness’ theory (Hamilton 1964);
  • Selection pressures leading to teamwork , reciprocal altruism (Trivers 1971; Maynard Smith 1982; Axelrod 1984) and indirect reciprocity (Alexander 1987; Joyce 2006); and
  • Group selection (Sober and Wilson 1998).

It would take us too far afield to survey all these biological accounts in detail, the background for which is already treated in the entry for biological altruism ; there are also many excellent and accessible summaries of such accounts and their application to psychological altruism (e.g., Joyce 2006, ch. 1). We will settle here for one detailed illustration of one way in which biological altruism can be given an evolutionary explanation, followed by a sketch of the ways in which this and other evolutionary mechanisms might likewise explain the emergence of psychological altruism—keeping in mind that this is all just one part of explaining morality proper, to which we return in the next sub-section.

The very idea that biological altruism can come about through natural selection may initially seem puzzling. One way of characterizing natural selection, after all, is in terms of “selfish genes”: natural selection occurs when a variant of a gene (an allele) at a given locus tends to cause a modification of a bodily or behavioral trait (a phenotypic trait) in a way that, in the overall environment, tends to cause that variant of the gene to increase its relative frequency in the next generation; this then increases the representation of the associated trait modification as well. Typically this happens when the phenotypic modification is one that causes the organism to have greater reproductive success: if, in the overall context, allele A causes its carrier to have a trait T that causes the organism to have more offspring than other organisms in the population who carry rival allele A* and display alternative trait T*, then A will be inherited and carried by more organisms in succeeding generations; and that means that T will likewise be displayed by more organisms (Dawkins, 1989). But how do we get from “selfish genes” increasing their representation in the gene pool, via improving the reproductive success of their carriers, to such things as cooperation and biological altruism? It turns out there are many ways.

To take one dramatic example, consider social insect colonies, and in particular, the Hymenoptera (bees, ants and wasps). In these colonies we find such an extreme degree of cooperation—division of labor (queen, workers, soldiers, etc.), food-sharing, information sharing—that it is tempting to view the entire colony as a single functioning organism. Indeed, in the case of stinging worker honey bees, there is not only cooperative labor but also, when necessary, the ultimate sacrifice in defense of the hive (at least where the invader is a mammal, stinging of which proves fatal to the bee as the barbed sting is torn out upon being deposited in the victim). How can such striking cooperation and self-sacrifice be explained in evolutionary terms?

One important fact to notice is that the colony is one large family: typically, the workers are sisters—daughters of the queen. Return to the idea of “selfish genes” described above: what ultimately increases an allele’s representation in the gene pool is its having some phenotypic effect that causes copies of that allele to be in more organisms in succeeding generations. That normally happens when the phenotypic effect causes the organism to have greater reproductive success, but it can equally happen if it causes the organism’s close kin to have greater reproductive success: for close kin are likely to carry copies of that same allele, which means that greater reproductive success for kin likewise propagates copies of the allele. So while an allele that causes an organism to engage in sex more often may thereby spread, so might an allele that causes an organism to help a sibling to reproduce (as by aiding survival); either way, that allele will be helping to propagate copies of itself in the next generation, which in turn means that the helping behavior it causes will likewise spread over time (Dawkins 1989, 171–77).

This mechanism of “kin selection” can explain how worker bees evolved such apparently ‘selfless’ traits, focused on aiding the queen’s survival and reproduction. In fact, the situation is even more interesting and extreme: workers have evolved to serve the queen’s reproduction at the complete expense of their own, as they are sterile . This extreme biological altruism, however, may be explained by the same principles, with the addition of the fact that due to a genetic peculiarity of the Hymenoptera (their haplodiploidy), sisters are more closely related to each other genetically than they would be to their own offspring. [ 4 ] This means that natural selection will actually favor worker traits that help their mother reproduce (thus making more sisters, who are especially likely to carry copies of the gene for that same trait, making it spread), over traits in workers aimed at personal reproduction. This could explain how worker sterility evolved, as traits focused on helping the queen took precedence over personal reproduction, and it explains how even suicidal behavior could have been selected for as propagating the genes that cause it (Dawkins 1989, 174–75). (It is worth noting, however, that the theory of kin selection and inclusive fitness is highly complex and has received renewed critical scrutiny in recent years. For a recent special collection of articles on the topic see Royal Society Open Science on Inclusive Fitness ).

This is only one example of one way in which biological altruism can evolve: there are others, which are not restricted to kin and are explained using game-theoretic or group dynamic models (again, see the entry on biological altruism for details). The crucial point is just that any kind of genetically-based trait can evolve if it happens to have the right kind of feedback effect on the genes that influence it. This brings us, then, to the sort of trait we are more interested in: a disposition for psychological altruism , as defined above.

Again, while it may initially seem puzzling that evolution should give rise to psychological altruism, rather than merely to selfishness, there is nothing paradoxical about it: a genetically-based disposition for psychological altruism will evolve just in case such a trait, in the relevant circumstances, promotes the propagation of the genes that bring it about (and does so more effectively than alternative traits produced by rival alleles). And this can again happen in various ways.

The basic idea is that psychological altruistic dispositions can evolve as proximate mechanisms or “modules” for promoting the biological advantages relevant to the forms of selection listed above. In some cases, these adaptive psychological mechanisms will involve specifically targeted or conditional altruistic motivations, involving capacities for discrimination to focus benefits on kin or on reciprocators. In other cases, the selection pressures will give rise to less discriminating altruistic sentiments and tendencies as the simplest and most cost-effective mechanisms for promoting adaptive cooperative behaviors in a given environment. If our hominin ancestors tended to live in circumstances where the opportunities for ‘wasting’ altruism in non-fitness-enhancing ways (e.g., on ‘outsiders’) were sufficiently few and far between, then a simple, undiscriminating (though limited) sense of concern and altruism may have promoted fitness at far less cost than more discriminating forms, evolving more readily. One advantage of this hypothesis is that it might help explain some sorts of concern and altruism that are otherwise hard to make sense of in evolutionary terms.

For example, suppose you receive a letter from UNICEF soliciting contributions for health and nutrition programs for children in Darfur, and you are moved to send a check. This is not merely selective altruism toward kin or likely reciprocators, but altruism toward strangers who are in no position to reciprocate, and it might therefore seem puzzling from a purely biological point of view: such ‘indiscriminate altruism’ isn’t biologically adaptive in the way more selective altruism might be; your helping children in Darfur isn’t helping to propagate your own genes, so it may seem mysterious how such a trait could have evolved through natural selection. But a trait that is not presently adaptive may once have been. In the environment in which our hominin ancestors lived, where there was little positive contact with outsiders, even relatively indiscriminate altruism would tend to benefit kin or potential reciprocators, and so might have been a simple adaptive mechanism on the whole.

If so, then your presently non-adaptive altruistic behavior in our current global environment could in principle be an expression of an evolved, indiscriminate altruistic tendency—an adaptation that is largely no longer adaptive, and so would amount to a kind of ‘misfiring’ of formerly adaptive instincts (Dawkins 2006, 220–21; Kitcher 2006b). It would be in this way on a par with our taste for fatty foods—originally evolved for its adaptive effects though it is no longer beneficial in today’s fast food economy—though in the case of altruism the ‘misfiring’ has happier results. Of course, it’s also possible (as discussed in section 2.4) that your altruistic tendency isn’t itself an adaptation at all, but is instead rooted in values that you’ve developed, through moral reflection in your cultural context, independently of specific evolutionary influences. Or it may be some combination of the two.

This area of inquiry remains largely speculative, since it is one thing to develop models for how psychological altruism could in principle evolve, and quite another to show convincingly that a given form of natural selection has in fact played the relevant role in actual human evolutionary history. There may be doubts, for example, whether there was sufficient pair-wise engagement in iterated prisoner’s dilemma games to explain the evolution of reciprocal altruism according to some of the most familiar game-theoretic models (Kitcher 2006a,b). In any case, it is time to return to the issue of moral judgment, which is crucial to the explanation of morality proper, and goes beyond mere altruistic feeling and behavior. The following sub-section describes one leading hypothesis.

Kitcher (2006a,b; 2011) has proposed a three-stage account of the evolution of morality. It begins with the evolution of an early but fragile form of psychological altruism among hominins in the context of “coalition games” in mixed adult groups. The social structure would have been similar to that of contemporary chimpanzees and bonobos, where cooperation among the relatively weak (or those in weak stages of life) is beneficial to them, but strategic calculation is infeasible. These conditions may have led from simpler forms of biological altruism developed through kin selection to the evolution of a psychological altruistic disposition involving “a blind tendency to respond to the preferences of another animal with whom you might engage in cooperative activity,” as a simple but effective mechanism for promoting advantageous participation in coalitions and subcoalitions (Kitcher 2006b). (This is the ‘indiscriminate’ altruism discussed in the previous sub-section.)

Because this disposition was both limited and unstable, however, and competed with powerful selfish drives, there was a continual threat of social rupture and loss of cooperative advantage. This in turn would have made ongoing peacemaking a necessity, thus limiting the size of viable cooperative units and the scope of cooperative projects, as well as imposing significant costs through the devotion of time and energy to peacemaking activities. An example would be extensive mutual grooming going well beyond what is necessary for hygiene, of the sort found in chimpanzee societies.

The next phase, according to this hypothesis, was a transition to much larger groups with more extensive cooperative activities, through the evolution of a capacity for emotionally laden normative guidance , without which such arrangements would not have been possible. (See also Gibbard 1990, ch. 4.) With the emergence of a capacity to make and follow normative judgments, reinforced by coevolved reactive emotions such as guilt and resentment, and the development of rules and social practices promoting and enforcing group loyalty and cooperation, a new psychological mechanism came into being for reinforcing the previously unstable altruistic tendencies and promoting large-scale social cohesion and stability. The advantages of membership in coalitions and subcoalitions would be conferred on hominins who had facility with such normative guidance—including a strong sense of obligation and tendency toward social compliance—and who thus acted consistently on these altruistic tendencies, acquiring the reputation for being good coalition partners and participating in a broader array of cooperative projects.

If this hypothesis is correct, it might explain not only the origins of our general capacity for normative judgment and motivation, but also the widespread tendency for social rules or norms historically to emphasize such things as group identity, loyalty and cohesion , and to focus largely on the regulation of violence and sex ; and it might help to explain widespread dispositions toward social conformity, concern with reputation and social standing, tendencies for group-wise scorning or punishment of the disloyal, and the power of emotions such as resentment, guilt and shame .

In the final phase, this sort of “proto-morality” of norms and reactive emotions would then be supplemented over thousands of years with various paths of cultural evolution , leading to the development and fleshing out of the much more sophisticated systems of moral beliefs, practices and institutions with which we are familiar, from the earliest historical examples right up to our present moral cultures (Kitcher 2006a, 2011). There is, of course, a great deal of leeway in the last part, concerning the details of the transition through cultural evolution from hominin proto-moralities to contemporary moral systems, which allows for some very different possible stories. Some accounts will attribute great influence to evolved, “domain-specific psychological modules” (such as a dedicated mechanism that automatically generates a feeling of concern when confronted with suffering) in shaping the content of our moral feeling, judgment and behavior, both through shaping our cultures and more directly; other accounts, while not denying some such influence, will emphasize very different factors as influencing the content of at least some of our moral beliefs (such as the “capacity for open-ended normativity” cited by Buchanan and Powell 2015, 2018, 2019). This brings us to the next major topic.

So far, we have focused on scientific projects that treat morality in the empirical sense as calling simply for causal explanation, as by appeal to evolutionary influences. This is unexceptionable with regard to the origins of the general human capacity for moral judgment: clearly some causal explanation is required, and an evolutionary explanation is plausible. But things are much more complicated when we consider the explanation of the actual content of moral judgment, feeling and behavior.

We have had a taste above of the way in which scientists might propose to explain our particular moral attitudes or judgments by appeal to specific evolutionary causes as filtered through cultural developments. Human beings have a strong, emotionally-laden sense of basic fairness, resentment of cheaters, and a desire that they be punished, all of which finds expression in both cultural norms and individual moral judgments. You might experience such feelings if you’ve been the victim of a scam, morally condemning the perpetrators. And some of these psychological traits may have analogues in other species. For example, Sarah Brosnan and Frans de Waal (2014) argue that “evidence indicates that [ inequity aversion , i.e., negative reactions to unequal rewards for similar tasks] is widespread in cooperative species under many circumstances”--though some have disputed this and offered alternative hypotheses to explain the behavior, based on further research (Engelmann, Clift, Herrmann, and Tomasello 2017). [ 5 ] In the simplest case, an animal protests when it sees a companion receive a superior reward for a similar task, as in a well-known study with brown capuchin monkeys, though similar effects have now been observed even in non-primates, such as dogs and crows. In the more complex case, chimpanzees sometimes react negatively to inequity even where they are the ones receiving the greater reward. A natural evolutionary hypothesis for the simpler case is that such a disposition protected against ‘wasting’ cooperative efforts where they were not fitness-enhancing. Similarly, a natural explanatory hypothesis for the more complex form of inequity aversion is that it evolved in creatures with sufficient predictive capacities and emotional control because it preserved beneficial cooperative relationships that could be threatened by such inequities, thus proving fitness-enhancing on the whole given the benefits of continued cooperation (Brosnan and de Waal, 2014). All of this might suggest good prospects for causal explanation of human moral traits in terms of evolved psychological traits. Indeed, Brosnan and de Waal explicitly hypothesize that the evolved complex response observed in champanzees is what “allowed the development of a complete sense of fairness in humans, which aims not at equality for its own sake but for the sake of continued cooperation” (Brosnan and de Waal, 2014).

Caution is needed here, however. Our moral judgments and resulting behaviors cannot just be assumed to be mere causal upshots of some such biological and psychological forces, on a par with the cooperative activity of bees or the resentment felt by capuchin monkeys (or even the broader unease apparently felt by chimpanzees) over unequal rewards for equal work. When a rational agent makes a judgment, whether in the sphere of morality or in such areas as science, mathematics or philosophy, the proper question is not in the first instance what caused that judgment to occur, but what reasons the person had for making it—for thinking it to be true. It is those reasons that typically constitute an explanation of the judgment. They explain by bringing out what the person took (rightly or wrongly) to be the justification for the belief in question—the considerations showing the belief likely to be true. All of this complicates the explanatory project in relation to the thoughts, feelings and actions of rational agents.

It is helpful to illustrate the general point first with other kinds of judgment, and then to return to morality. Consider some judgments in mathematics, philosophy and science:

M: There is at least one prime number between 5,000 and 10,000. P: If identity claims such as ‘water = H 2 O’ are true, then they are necessary truths (i.e., true in all possible worlds). S: There is no such thing as absolute simultaneity.

How do we explain someone’s believing something like M, P or S? We normally need to know her reasons for believing it to be true, which we can then go on to assess as good or bad reasons for such a belief. Either way, we typically take her reasons—and the reasoning associated with them—to explain her belief, which is why we engage seriously with her reasons as such in critical discussion, and go on to inquire into their merits. If, for example, we ask a person why she believes M, and she cites a proof she has found convincing, showing that for any natural number n > 1 there is at least one prime number between n and 2 n , we normally take this as a sufficient explanation for why she believes M. What we do not normally do is to appeal directly to independent causes, such as evolutionary or other biological or psychological influences to explain people’s beliefs in these areas. Such independent explanations for beliefs can sometimes be correct, as in the case of someone given a post-hypnotic suggestion, in which case we may regard her judgment as merely caused and the reasons offered as mere rationalization. But this is not the norm.

The reason why we normally explain beliefs such as M, P or S by appeal to the reasons the person gives for them is that we normally assume that the person is capable of intelligent reflection and reasoning and has arrived at her belief for the reasons she gives as a result of that reflection (whether or not the belief is ultimately correct). We assume in general that people are capable of significant autonomy in their thinking, in the following sense:

Autonomy Assumption : people have, to greater or lesser degrees, a capacity for reasoning that follows autonomous standards appropriate to the subjects in question , rather than in slavish service to evolutionarily given instincts merely filtered through cultural forms or applied in novel environments. Such reflection, reasoning, judgment and resulting behavior seem to be autonomous in the sense that they involve exercises of thought that are not themselves significantly shaped by specific evolutionarily given tendencies, but instead follow independent norms appropriate to the pursuits in question (Nagel 1979).

This assumption seems hard to deny in the face of such abstract pursuits as algebraic topology, quantum field theory, population biology, modal metaphysics, or twelve-tone musical composition, all of which seem transparently to involve precisely such autonomous applications of human intelligence . Even if there are evolutionary influences behind our general tendency to engage in certain kinds of mental activity, or behind some of our motives in these pursuits (e.g., if a given musician or poet is motivated to compose music or poetry in order to impress a potential mate), this would not show that the activity is governed in its details by such influences (cf. Buchanan and Powell 2015, 2018, and 2019). And again, this assumption of autonomy is borne out in our normal explanations of beliefs such as P above: we take a person at her word that what explains her believing P, for example, is that due to philosophical arguments she’s read and has found convincing she takes ‘water’ to work like a proper name and thinks that it follows from this that ‘water’ refers to whatever molecular compound it picks out in the actual world in all possible worlds in which the compound exists.

Few would deny the autonomy assumption altogether. To do so in the name of providing alternative evolutionary causal explanations of our beliefs would risk self-defeat: for if we lack the relevant intellectual autonomy across the board, then even the biologist’s beliefs about evolutionary biology and its implications would just be attributable to such biological causes, rather than to reasons that provide real warrant for such beliefs within a rational framework with truth-tracking integrity. The challenge to the autonomy assumption is therefore more likely to come in a selective form. [ 6 ]

This brings us back to moral judgment. As with M, P and S, people typically have reasons for their moral judgments, and whether or not we agree with them, we typically take those reasons to explain why they believe what they do. Consider again the moral judgment mentioned earlier:

MJ: The person who cheated me did something wrong and should be punished.

Just as with M, P and S, someone making this judgment will have reasons that she takes to justify this claim, ultimately tying into her overall conception of right and wrong. And we tend to take this at face value as an explanation of why she believes MJ, unless we have special reason to suspect distorting causes, such as prejudice leading to misperception and rationalization. We tend to think that a person has the moral beliefs she does as a result of background moral reflection and reasoning, within her cultural context. In other words, we tend to treat a person’s moral beliefs much as we treat her reasoned mathematical, scientific, or philosophical beliefs, applying the autonomy assumption in seeking to explain why she believes what she does.

One potential lesson from evolutionary biology, however, is that even if the autonomy assumption equally applies in principle to the sphere of moral judgment, it may be a mistake just to assume that most moral judgment and behavior is in fact a result of the exercise of such autonomous reflection, reasoning and judgment. The autonomy assumption, after all, says only that we have the capacity for relevantly autonomous reflection and judgment; it does not imply that we always exercise it. Perhaps the human capacity for autonomous thinking is exercised only in some cases, while in others the process that leads to moral belief is largely influenced by evolved psychological dispositions, such as emotional adaptations. While such a situation may not tend to arise in relation to our mathematical, philosophical, or scientific thinking, our evolutionary history may have given rise to emotional dispositions that play a significant role in at least some of our moral thinking, feeling and behavior. (See section 2.5 below.)

One plausible story, then, is that while many of our more reflective and reasoned moral judgments involve autonomous exercises of domain-general intelligence, many other less reflective moral judgments are largely attributable to evolutionary influences—both through direct conditioning of people’s moral judgments by evolved, domain-specific psychological dispositions and through background influences on cultural factors. On this hypothesis, we cannot treat moral judgments as a homogeneous set, but must recognize that they can come about in very different ways, requiring a plurality of explanatory models. While a model of autonomous reasoning might apply to some moral beliefs and behaviors, a model appealing to evolutionary causal influences will apply to others. And often some combination of models may be necessary, as in cases where both evolutionary influences and our own independent moral reflection might lead to similar judgments, overdetermining them.

For example, even if it is true that evolutionary pressures favoring caring for offspring have strongly influenced our attitudes towards our children, it does not follow that this is the complete explanation for why we believe we have special obligations to care for our children and for why we behave as we do toward them. It may be part of the explanation, while another part may have to do with an autonomous recognition of the appropriateness of special parental care: we see that we have good reasons to take special care of our children, which ought to motivate us even if we weren’t already motivated by instinctive feelings. We might also employ autonomous, domain-general comprehensive moral reasoning to recognize that our instinctive feelings shouldn’t always be followed, e.g., in cases where considerations of justice constrain certain pursuits of benefits for one’s own children, providing genuine overriding reasons to refrain from unjust actions. (We will consider another plausible example of overdetermination involving judgments about the much discussed ‘Trolley cases’ in section 3.)

Advocates of an autonomous reflection model of moral judgment grant that various causal influences—likely including evolutionary ones—often play some role in moral thought and feeling. But opponents who hold a deflationary view of the role of autonomous reflection seek to press the challenge here more fully. To expand the potential reach of the evolutionary influence model of moral judgment, they typically combine that causal model with what may be called the ‘mere rationalization hypothesis’ with regard to the reasons people give for moral judgments that are really shaped by evolutionary factors.

On this view, our giving of reasons for our moral beliefs in such cases is interpreted as mere post hoc rationalization . Rather than engaging in autonomous reflection and reasoning, and coming to believe certain moral propositions for the reasons that emerge from that reflection (as with M, P and S), what is happening instead according to this hypothesis is that (1) our moral beliefs are simply caused by emotions or ‘moral instincts’ we have largely due to our evolutionary background, and (2) we then invent rationalizations for these resulting beliefs in order to try to make sense of them to ourselves, unaware of their real causal origins (Haidt 2001; Wheatley and Haidt 2005; Knobe and Leiter 2007; Leiter 2007).

For example, when someone judges that abortion is wrong, it may be that “the anti-abortion judgment (a gut feeling that abortion is bad) causes the belief that life begins at conception (an ex post facto rationalization of the gut feeling)” (Haidt 2001, 817). On this model, our moral reasonings and justifications (or at least those to which the model is supposed to apply) are just so much window dressing for beliefs that are more like post-hypnotic suggestions than they are like M, P or S; just as with post-hypnotic suggestions, people go to great lengths to provide rationalizations in an attempt to render their moral beliefs intelligible to themselves. The difference is that instead of a hypnotist, the causal agents are emotional dispositions stemming from our evolutionary past.

The basic idea that some moral beliefs are susceptible to this sort of debunking explanation is not new. Moral philosophers have long recognized that people have often been led to moral judgments based on self-interest or prejudice, for example, and then rationalized their views, inventing justifications for positions held due to other causes. A plausible example would be a judgment such as:

MJ2: Interracial marriage is morally wrong.

While such a judgment was not uncommon just a few generations ago, most readers of this article will recognize MJ2 to be not only false, but also likely to have stemmed from racial prejudice, with much of what was said to justify it being mere post hoc rationalization for a view more attributable to the causal influence of prejudice than to the workings of autonomous reflection and reasononing. Most philosophers today would say something similar about a moral belief still held by many people, especially within traditional religions:

MJ3: Homosexuality is morally wrong.

The reason why philosophers tend to find a ‘mere rationalization hypothesis’ plausible for such beliefs as MJ2 and MJ3 is that (i) the justifications offered for them have consistently failed to stand up to critical reflection, and (ii) there are plausible alternative explanations for why people have really come to hold such beliefs, such as that they have misconstrued personal feelings of disgust as perceptions of objective moral wrongness, and projected those feelings onto the world as ‘moral impurity’. [ 7 ] Together, these considerations lend support to the hypothesis that the justifications offered are mere rationalizations, and that the beliefs are best explained by appeal to emotional causes.

The central question is: How broadly does the deflationary model of the ‘mere rationalization hypothesis’ apply to moral judgments, and to what extent are evolutionary influences implicated in those cases?

At one extreme, someone might deny that the autonomy assumption applies to the moral domain at all: we either lack these capacities in the domain of moral thought, or at least never exercise them. Such a claim seems to have little plausibility, however. Why should it be that human intelligence and innovation know virtually no bounds in other domains—as illustrated by feats of autonomous inquiry and creativity in quantum field theory, algebraic topology, modal metaphysics, or symphonic composition—and yet when it comes to moral thinking we remain stuck in ruts carved out for us by evolution, slavishly following patterns of thought prescribed for us by evolved, domain-specific mechanisms, with all of our cultural developments providing mere variations on those themes?

The very fact of human self-consciousness makes such a picture unlikely: for as soon as we are told that our thinking is constrained along evolutionarily given paths, our very awareness of those influences provides the opening to imagine and to pursue new possibilities. If you are told, for example, that you are evolutionarily conditioned to favor your group heavily over outsiders in your moral judgments, you are able, as a reflective agent, to take this very fact into account in your subsequent moral reflection, deciding that this favoring is unwarranted and thus coming to a new, more egalitarian moral view. [ 8 ] Analogously, it may be true that we possess dedicated mechanisms for ‘reading’ faces as trustworthy or threatening, and often make split-second judgments on this basis; but this doesn’t preclude our ability to revise such judgments, as when we reflect on the behavior of someone with ‘trustworthy facial features’ and realize that he is actually a scoundrel.

It is noteworthy that the leading proponent of the mere rationalization hypothesis, Jonathan Haidt (2001), does not take the extreme position of denying the autonomy assumption. He grants that such capacities exist and are sometimes exercised, singling out the moral deliberations of philosophers as likely examples (2001, 828–29). His claim is just that such exercise of autonomous reasoning in the production of moral judgment is rare; in the vast majority of cases, our judgments result from immediate ‘intuitions’ reflecting emotional causation. But there are many questions to raise even about this qualified claim (despite its generously letting philosophers, at least, off the hook).

Even where our judgments are based on immediate ‘intuitions’, it may be that these intuitions are often themselves informed by prior acts of reflection and reasoning (Pizarro and Bloom 2003), or are partly cognitive responses to objective features of situations that may outrun our ability (prior to philosophical reflection) to articulate them—much as a chess master may ‘see’ that a certain move is best prior to being able to articulate exactly why (Kamm 1996, 2007). Similarly, the input from the autonomous reasoning of philosophers and some religious leaders may well influence the background ethical sensibilities of whole societies, thus influencing moral judgment even where there is no lengthy reasoning occurring in the particular case. There are also important philosophical worries about the methodologies by which Haidt comes to his deflationary conclusions about the role played by reasoning in ordinary people’s moral judgments.

To take just one example, Haidt cites a study where people made negative moral judgments in response to “actions that were offensive yet harmless, such as…cleaning one’s toilet with the national flag.” People had negative emotional reactions to these things and judged them to be wrong, despite the fact that they did not cause any harms to anyone; that is, “affective reactions were good predictors of judgment, whereas perceptions of harmfulness were not” (Haidt 2001, 817). He takes this to support the conclusion that people’s moral judgments in these cases are based on gut feelings and merely rationalized, since the actions, being harmless, don’t actually warrant such negative moral judgments. But such a conclusion would be supported only if all the subjects in the experiment were consequentialists , specifically believing that only harmful consequences are relevant to moral wrongness. If they are not, and believe—perhaps quite rightly (though it doesn’t matter for the present point what the truth is here)—that there are other factors that can make an action wrong, then their judgments may be perfectly appropriate despite the lack of harmful consequences.

This is in fact entirely plausible in the cases studied: most people think that it is inherently disrespectful , and hence wrong, to clean a toilet with their nation’s flag, quite apart from the fact that it doesn’t hurt anyone; so the fact that their moral judgment lines up with their emotions but not with a belief that there will be harmful consequences does not show (or even suggest) that the moral judgment is merely caused by emotions or gut reactions. Nor is it surprising that people have trouble articulating their reasons when they find an action intrinsically inappropriate, as by being disrespectful (as opposed to being instrumentally bad, which is much easier to explain).

To return to our central question: it remains unclear just how much of human moral judgment is susceptible to the mere rationalization hypothesis, or when it is, how much of a role is played by evolutionary influences on emotions. The mere rationalization hypothesis is best supported when we have independent reason to reject an appeal to autonomous reflection, as when a moral judgment is implausible in itself and we have a very likely debunking causal explanation of why someone might nonetheless be led to believe such a thing. Such is the case with MJ2 and MJ3 above, and perhaps many other traditional moral judgments focused on sexual taboos, notions of ‘impurity’, in-group loyalty (from tribalism to nationalism), hierarchical authority relations, and rigid gender roles . But this does not provide grounds for a deflationary approach across the board.

Many moral beliefs—for example, concerning the moral irrelevance of sexual preference, the moral equality of persons of all races and nationalities, or moral obligations even to future generations in far away countries—are much more plausible candidates for being upshots of autonomous moral reflection and reasoning. Indeed, many philosophers take them to be plausible candidates for moral truths , grasped through reflection that reveals good reasons for believing them, which is therefore what explains our moral beliefs and behavior in these cases.

These claims may, of course, be disputed. Even if it is granted that our judgments are often the products of our reasoning, pace Haidt (2001), it remains possible that our reasoning itself is distorted by evolutionary influences. This may be especially worrisome given the role played by intuitions in moral reasoning (unlike with mathematical reasoning, say), even in determining our acceptance of premises in arguments: insofar as there are concerns that our intuitions may be distorted by evolutionary influences, there will equally be worries about our moral reasoning (Sinnott-Armstrong 2005).

It remains unclear, however, just how far such worries really extend, even if it is granted that moral intuition and reasoning are often subject to such distorting influence. It is hard to see, for example, how some people’s moral belief that we should impoverish ourselves and limit our own reproduction in order to help distant strangers, or even that we should cease having children altogether, could be explained in terms of the distortion of their reasoning by evolutionary influences. The striking range of moral beliefs itself, both across and within cultures, seems like good evidence of significant input from autonomous moral reflection—moral thought going beyond exercises of evolved “neurocomputational systems” or “social contract algorithms” or “inference engines” with domain-specific goals and special inference procedures designed for solving particular adaptive problems (Cosmides and Tooby 2008). Even if there are indeed such special modules devoted to reasoning about obligation and entitlement, as posited by evolutionary psychologists, the question is how much they explain, and whether they really exclude significant input from autonomous moral reasoning.

These issues remain challenging and controversial. But the controversies are as much ongoing philosophical ones as scientific ones, and it is therefore unlikely that scientific results will settle them. Science will plainly not settle, for example, whether or not there are moral truths; and if there are, they will likely play an explanatory role with regard to at least some of our moral beliefs—something we will miss if we approach these issues from an exclusively scientific point of view.

A duly cautious claim about the explanatory role of evolution with respect to morality in the empirical sense might therefore be:

The Modest Evolutionary Explanatory Thesis : evolutionary forces may adequately explain certain capacities and tendencies associated with moral thinking, feeling and behavior, and may explain or partially explain some of the content of our moral thought, feeling and behavior, insofar as it is influenced (individually or via influences on cultural development) by those tendencies.

3. Evolutionary Biology and Normative Ethics: Prescriptive Evolutionary Ethics, Corrective Evolutionary Ethics, and the Question of Moral Progress

In section 1.2, we distinguished between the empirical and normative senses of ‘morality’. This section deals with morality in the normative sense . Does evolutionary biology shed light on the content of morality in the normative sense? That is, in thinking about how we ought to live, do we get any insight from evolutionary theory? And does evolutionary biology have any significant implications for thinking about the prospects for moral progress?

The project of attempting to derive normative conclusions from the facts of evolutionary biology is most commonly associated with Herbert Spencer and his “Social Darwinist” admirers. Spencer was, by all accounts, a more gifted and subtle thinker than he is typically given credit for today. (See the entry on Spencer .) Still, we may treat his views briefly here, as his arguments concerning evolutionary biology and ethics were based on deep misunderstandings of evolution. This is not to deny the historical interest of his views. It may be surprising to learn, for example, that Spencer himself gave a central place to harmony and mutual aid in the “permanently peaceful societies” he viewed as the pinnacle of evolution in its “highest phase”—something one does not typically associate with “Social Darwinism”, but which comes directly from Spencer’s (largely non-Darwinian) conception of evolution.

Spencer (1879) conceived of evolution as a teleological process, directed toward the production of progressively “more evolved” (in the sense of “superior”) forms manifesting a greater “totality of life”, i.e., a greater richness of thought, feeling and action, as well as greater length of life. Human behavior is “more evolved” than the behavior of other animals, and the harmonious and mutually supportive behavior of people in “permanently peaceful societies” (where “self-maintenance and race-maintenance” is pursued without hindering others in the same pursuit) is “more evolved” than the behavior of savages or of members of less harmonious societies; that is, the former is the “highest form of conduct” because it subserves the greatest “totality of life” embodied by harmonious and happy human social life, where the latter is taken to be the final end of evolution.

All of this, of course, is inconsistent with Darwinism, which denies that evolution is a teleological or end-directed process, gives no meaning to Spencer’s notions of “more evolved” forms or conduct (whereby human beings, for example, are “more evolved” than other species, or ethical conduct is “more evolved” than unethical conduct), and focuses on reproductive fitness rather than on Spencer’s notion of the “greatest totality of life in self, in offspring and in fellow man,” among other fundamental differences (Rachels 1990). Spencer’s views on morality and evolution may therefore be set aside as historically interesting but unhelpful to contemporary discussions based on a better understanding of evolutionary biology.

Even philosophers sympathetic to ethical naturalism (the view that moral facts are themselves natural facts of some sort) have typically been wary of attempts to derive conclusions about morality in the normative sense from facts about evolutionary history. This is especially so when they are clear (unlike Spencer) about the principles governing Darwinian evolution through natural selection. From the fact that a certain trait is an adaptation, which evolved through natural selection by virtue of its positive feedback effects on germ-line replication of the alleles that generate the trait, nothing at all seems to follow about whether it is morally good or right, or something we ought to embrace and foster. Certain dispositions may be present in us for good evolutionary reasons without any implication that these traits benefit us, or are moral virtues or produce behaviors that are morally right.

A brief survey of some of the traits that are likely biological adaptations in a number of species—such as a tendency to kill ‘step-children’ or to philander—ought to convince us that even if similar tendencies are likewise adaptations in human beings, present in us for similar evolutionary reasons, this would be no argument at all that we ought to engage in such behaviors. Clearly the burden would be on the prescriptive evolutionary ethicist to explain why a trait’s having been good at propagating the alleles coding for it tens or hundreds of thousands of years ago should be thought to have anything at all with the rational or moral justification of our embracing it . And the prospects for meeting this burden have never seemed strong: it is hard to see how such evolutionary facts can possibly have normative authority or force for a rational agent (McDowell 1995). Regardless of why one has a given trait, the question for a rational agent is always: is it right for me to exercise it, or should I instead renounce and resist it as far as I am able? (Korsgaard 2006). [ 9 ]

This suggests that ethics, like mathematics, is an autonomous subject in the sense that it has its own “internal standards of justification and criticism”, such that its conclusions cannot be justified by other forms of inquiry such as evolutionary biology (Nagel 1979, 142; McDowell 1995 and 1997a,b). Normative ethical conclusions are justified through first-order ethical reflection and argument, just as mathematical propositions are justified through mathematical reasoning, rather than through learning more about our evolutionary past or about what is happening in our brains when we engage in these forms of reasoning (Rachels, 1990). It would seem to be as much of a mistake to try to answer ethical questions by examining fMRI scans or studying our evolutionary history as it would be to try to solve mathematical problems by such means (except, perhaps, insofar as evolutionary theory may shed light on some present, morally relevant empirical facts, as discussed below).

Still, some have argued that empirical psychological studies (and related evolutionary hypotheses—see section 4.2) can have normative ethical implications. In particular, it has recently been argued that scientific evidence supports consequentialist ethical theories over deontological ones (Greene 2003, 2008, Singer 2005). Consider a famous pair of hypothetical cases much discussed by moral philosophers (Thomson 1985):

Trolley : a runaway trolley is heading toward five people on the track ahead, who cannot get out of the way; it cannot be stopped, but there is a switch you could flip that would divert it onto a side track containing only one person; Bridge : a runaway trolley is heading toward five people on the track ahead, who cannot get out of the way; you are standing on a bridge over the track, and if you shove the very large person next to you off the bridge and in front of the trolley, the crushing of his body will stop the trolley before it reaches the five.

Most people respond to these cases by saying that Trolley is permissible while Bridge is not. But what explains this difference in moral response? Many philosophers have argued for deontological constraints prohibiting murdering some to save others, as in Bridge; they regard the case of diverting a public threat toward lesser harm, as in Trolley, as an exception, and offer principled reasons for doing so, thus justifying our treating the two cases differently (e.g., Thomson 1985). Greene (2008, 42–44) dismisses such normative explanations as unconvincing and takes a very different tack, highlighting another difference between Trolley and Bridge: whereas the harm done in Bridge (shoving a man to his death) is “up close and personal”, the harm done in Trolley (by flipping a switch) is not. This difference corresponds to a difference in the strength of emotional response, the response to “personal” harm being much stronger; and this in turn corresponds to a difference in the brain regions most active when the cases are contemplated: Bridge tends to activate areas associated with social/emotional processing (the posterior cingulate cortex, the medial prefrontal cortex, and the amygdala) while Trolley produces activity in areas associated with higher cognition (the dorsolateral prefrontal cortex and the inferior parietal lobe).

Greene takes this to support the hypothesis that what accounts for people’s different moral responses to Trolley and Bridge (and countless other cases) is simply the difference in emotional response, which in turn ties in to evolutionary explanations. Given the need in our evolutionary past for mechanisms to restrain interpersonal violence within cooperating groups, “it should come as no surprise if we have innate responses to personal violence that are powerful but rather primitive,” predating the evolution of complex reasoning and now competing with our more reasoned responses (Greene 2008, 43). Deontological intuitions, such as our condemnation of the violence in Bridge, thus represent evolved “alarm-like emotional responses” which are subsequently rationalized rather than resulting from moral reasoning (see the discussion of Haidt in section 2.5); by contrast, our responses to more abstract harm such as Trolley reflect complex cognitive processes, as do consequentialist responses generally, including cases where people overcome their initial negative emotional responses (in cases like Bridge) and decide that the right thing to do is whatever produces the best overall consequences.

Greene’s claim, then, is that this casts doubt on deontological ethical theory: far from giving us good reasons to refrain from certain utility maximizing acts, it merely gives expression to emotional relics of our evolutionary history. A rational morality will move beyond such alarm-like emotions and take us, through genuine reasoning, in the direction of consequentialism.

As with Haidt’s claims about moral judgment (section 2.5), there are many philosophical questions to raise about such appeals to experimental data to draw philosophically loaded conclusions (Appiah 2008, Berker 2009, Dancy 2014, Railton 2014, FitzPatrick 2018). It is hardly surprising, after all, that people have strong emotional reactions to blatant rights violations such as shoving an innocent person off a bridge in front of a trolley to be crushed for the greater good. Such emotions would equally be expected on deontological models. Nor does the speed with which we make negative moral judgments in such cases show that the judgments are merely emotion-driven: even if there is not explicit reasoning going on in each case, the emotion-laden intuitive responses may be informed by background moral reflection and formation (Pizarro and Bloom 2003, Dancy 2014, Railton 2014). Philosophers who are less skeptical of the normative explanations for our judgments will find it plausible that such reflection has made us intuitively sensitive to morally relevant distinctions—such as the distinction between doing something to a public threat to direct it toward least harm vs. assaulting an innocent person and using his harm to bring about less overall harm; that sensitivity then shows up in our intuitive moral judgments, which are no less justified just because they provoke strong emotions.

Indeed, philosophers who believe there are good reasons for distinguishing morally between Trolley and Bridge are unlikely to be convinced by the above debunking explanation, for the following reason. Suppose we vary Bridge to equalize the cases for the factor Greene emphasizes: instead of having to shove the man off the bridge, all you have to do in Bridge Lever is flip a switch, and the switch will activate a lever that knocks the bystander off the bridge in front of the trolley. These cases are now equalized to be “impersonal”: neither now involves violence that is “up close and personal”. But does this variation change our moral response? If it does not, and we find Bridge Lever again objectionable (just like Bridge) while allowing for Trolley, then Greene’s proposed explanation would not work: we would need a different explanation for this pair of cases, such as the reason-giving explanation deontological philosophers would give. Even with regard to the original pair of cases, while Greene may be right that evolved dispositions against personal violence play some role in explaining our reactions, this needn’t be the whole explanation. It may be that this is another case of overdetermination (see section 2.4).

A less problematic kind of appeal to evolutionary theory has been made even by those who fully recognize the autonomy of ethics and the role of autonomous moral reflection. Darwinian evolutionary theory implies that many other beliefs about the natures and origins of living things are false. Human beings are not members of a species created by a special act of a divine designer, but members of an evolved species related by common ancestry to every other species on Earth. So insofar as certain ethical views rely on assumptions about special creation, they will be refuted by the success of evolutionary theory. More weakly, insofar as certain ethical views have traditionally been supported by claims about special creation, they will to that extent lose some of their support. This would not show that they are false or even unjustified, as there may be alternative sufficient support for them. But in removing some of their common support, evolutionary theory would pose a significant challenge to those who had relied on that support (Rachels 1990).

Rachels takes such an approach against the common belief that human beings have a special moral dignity that is much higher than the status enjoyed by non-human animals. Such a belief has traditionally been rooted in the idea that we are separate from other living things, having been created specially in the image of God and endowed with souls, giving us a special moral status. If evolutionary theory is true, however, then this support is undermined: since Homo sapiens evolved from other species, there is no sharp biological separation between Homo sapiens and the rest of the living world; there is instead a continuum through evolutionary history, with no species created separately, in a divine image, or infused with special souls. Thus, those who have based their beliefs about the speical moral status of human beings on a creationist picture have a problem: that picture is false, and the true picture does nothing to support such a view.

Again, however, this does not show that the common view of special human dignity is false or even unjustified. There may be other forms of support for it that do not depend on creationist assumptions. Many would argue, for example, that although we are related to other animals, we are very different from even our closest primate relatives, as (not to put too fine a point on it) a trip to the zoo followed by a visit to the Library of Congress or the Metropolitan Museum of Art will confirm. The vastness of the differences between human and other forms of life on Earth is not erased by pointing out that human beings got to be the way we are through contingent evolutionary processes acting on brains similar to those of extant apes, together with thousands of years of cultural evolution. It is these real differences—regardless of how they came about—that plausibly ground differences in the moral status of human beings and other animals. [ 10 ]

There are more straightforward ways in which evolutionary biology, as well as results from empirical moral psychology, can play a corrective role in normative ethics. Evolutionary biology and comparative genetics might, for example, be used to undermine false claims about race, which underlie racist ethical claims. Experimental psychology might be used to cast doubts on the moral condemnation of homosexuality by supporting the debunking hypothesis that such judgments stem from projected disgust. More generally, psychological experiments can expose typical human pitfalls in moral judgment and behavior—tendencies toward cruelty in conditions of power inequality, or toward exaggerated moral condemnation when experiencing disgust or stress. If we understand these facts about ourselves, we can more effectively pursue and realize normative goals such as non-violence or fairness by avoiding circumstances that lead to cruelty, or by watching for and correcting distorting influences on our judgment (Glover 2000; Appiah 2008, 49, 71–72, 110–11, 124; Buchanan and Powell 2018). As noted earlier, however, the normative goals themselves will not have been set for us by evolutionary biology or psychology. That task falls to informed moral reflection.

The idea of moral progress features prominently in reflection on the history and future of moral thought and practice. While it may be difficult to assess whether a society has made moral progress on the whole over some period, it is not hard to find plausible examples of progress along particular dimensions. The elimination of the Atlantic slave trade, for example, and the development of the modern human rights movement are compelling examples of widespread moral progress. There are also plausible avenues to further progress through improved conformity with legitimate moral norms and through improvements in moral concepts, reasoning, and understanding. We might then wonder: what are the drivers of such moral progress (and likewise of moral regression when it occurs)? And how might evolutionary biology bear on the prospects and strategies for achieving moral progress (and avoiding moral regression)? Allen Buchanan and Russell Powell take up these issues in wide-ranging theoretical work that potentially has practical implications for a number of current social and political problems, as discussed below (Buchanan and Powell 2018, 2019; Buchanan 2020; see also the symposium discussion of the 2018 book in Analyse & Kritik 41(2), 2019).

Different metaethical stances (see section 4) yield different understandings of what moral progress might consist in as well as different explanations for how moral progress has historically come about. A moral realist, for example, will tend to conceive of moral progress in terms of achieving a more accurate grasp of objective moral truths and refining of our practices and institutions to align more closely with them; and plausible examples, such as the widespread liberalization of moral practices over the past few centuries, will be explained largely by appeal to growing insight into moral truth (Huemer 2016). By contrast, those who reject such appeals to objective moral truths but wish to retain some notion of moral progress (perhaps one that is extensionally very similar) will formulate a different conception of progress and offer socio-cultural explanations of progressive changes that do not rely on appeals to improved insights into moral truth (Kitcher 2011). We will here set aside the many complex issues attending these different approaches and focus on this question: what bearing might our evolutionary past have on our prospects and strategies for achieving the sorts of changes most agree would constitute moral progress?

Suppose that the trend toward greater inclusivity with respect to the scope of moral consideration—i.e., the elimination of racial and gender barriers to the attribution of full human moral status, and the extension of substantial moral considerability to a wide range of non-human animals—counts as moral progress. One pessimistic thought that might arise here on the basis of evolutionary considerations is that human moral psychology may have evolved in such a way as to place inevitable constraints on the possibilities for achieving robust and sustained progress in these respects. While our evolved moral psychology may contain certain altruistic elements, these may be ultimately parochial, given the nature of the selection pressures faced by our Pleistocene ancestors and assuming, as most discussions do, that the long Pleistocene Epoch (roughly 2.6 million years ago to 11,700 years ago, is the one primarily relevant to the biological evolution of human psychological traits). [ 11 ] That is, these elements may be focused on kin and members of a perceived in-group, with other countervailing dispositions posing strong obstacles to extending that altruism to outside groups. Even if we have some capacity for autonomous moral thought, enabling at least some to grasp more inclusive moral truths, there may be such powerful evolutionary constraints built into human moral psychology that such ideas are unlikely to take hold and motivate progressive changes in a widespread and sustainable way. There may be evolutionary limits to the basic moral progress that we evolved primates can realistically hope to achieve: we may just be saddled with a largely exclusivist, tribalist morality.

Buchanan and Powell refer to this pessimistic idea as “evoconservatism,” and they note that it has been used to argue against social and political movements organized around such “cosmopolitan moral reform.” And on the other side of that same evolutionary coin, “evoliberals” share the same premise about the constraints imposed by evolution on human moral psychology but instead argue that since the progressive goals are sufficiently desirable, we should look for biotechnological interventions to alter human nature in such a way as to make them realistically achievable. Buchanan and Powell reject both views because they reject the underlying picture of evolved human moral nature. Instead, they argue that the striking shifts that have already occurred toward more inclusive morality, as well as consideration of the conditions under which moral regression has occurred, support a very different, more nuanced picture of evolved human moral psychology—one without such pessimistic implications for deep and lasting moral progress.

On their “biocultural” view, it is not just that human rationality allows significant scope for autonomous moral reasoning that can lead to greater inclusivity (as discussed in section 2.4 above), but that our evolved moral psychology itself contains the seeds for such a shift (though it equally contains the seeds for potential moral regression). They key idea is that our evolved moral nature is neither inherently tribalist nor inherently inclusivist, but contains both dispositions; their expression, however, is conditional on the particular socio-institutional environmental conditions that obtain (or are at least perceived to obtain). In some conditions tribalistic dispositions will be engaged, while in other conditions inclusivist dispositions can dominate. This is their “adaptive plasticity” model of evolved human moral psychology, according to which evolution has disposed us to think and behave in certain ways under one set of (perceived) conditions, and in very different ways under another set of (perceived) conditions—this having been fitness-enhancing in our evolutionary history. In particular, our tribalist tendencies are activated when “cues of out-group threat” are perceived (whether real or not), involving competition, disease, undermining of in-group cohesion, and so on; by contrast, our inclusivist tendencies are activated when such cues are less abundant or salient.

The hypothesis is that these adaptively plastic traits served the biological interests of Pleiostocene humans well, achieving the joint benefits of tribalism under conditions where it was fitness-enhancing and more inclusive morality under conditions where tribalism was counterproductive and greater inclusivity was beneficial. For us today, this constitutes a mixed inheritance: on the one hand, it provides us with the seeds for moral progress insofar as we can foster and maintain the socio-institutional contexts that allow more inclusive dispositions to flourish; on the other hand, it saddles us with vulnerability to destructive tribalism when we find ourselves (or even just perceive ourselves to be) in circumstances characterized by sufficient out-group threat cues. Buchanan and Powell argue that this makes human beings dangerously susceptible to moral regression due to the manipulation of perceptions through demagogic populism, for example—a danger that is exacerbated where disinformation is rapidly spread through social media. If they are right, then the situation is ripe for media-savvy politicians to manipulate popular beliefs in ways designed to trigger the threat cues that energize tribalist tendencies in thought, feeling and behavior for political gain—from reflexive anti-immigrant nationalist sentiment to racially charged scapegoating during a pandemic.

While these dangers cast doubt on the conviction that moral progress is inevitable or even the natural default, the model proposed by Buchanan and Powell leaves open a realistic hope for continued and deepening moral progress: it is possible for humanity to make and sustain deep moral progress, without being hamstrung by any inbuilt evolutionary constraints; but it will require ongoing cultural efforts to foster and sustain the socio-institutional circumstances that enable the better aspects of human moral nature to predominate (Buchanan, forthcoming). This is the practical message of this biocultural theory of moral progress: moral progress is possible for us without the need for biotechnological modifications of human nature; but such progress is also fragile and cannot be taken for granted (Buchanan and Powell 2018).

4. Evolutionary Metaethics

While evolutionary facts may do little to illuminate the content of morality in the normative sense (apart from shedding light on morally relevant facts), they are sometimes thought to tell us something about the existence and nature of morality in the normative sense. (See section 1.2 for the notion of morality in the normative sense.) A number of philosophers have claimed that evolutionary theory can be used to debunk certain metaethical theories and perhaps to support others. One relatively modest project along these lines would be to use evolutionary biology to undermine Aristotelian appeals to natural teleology in human life to account for ethical facts, along the lines of Foot (2001). This evolutionary-based critique of “teleological naturalism” in ethics (FitzPatrick 2000) is discussed in the

Supplement on Natural Teleology in Ethics .

Other projects involve using evolutionary biology to try to undermine traditional moral realism —the view that moral judgments can be true (accurately representing moral facts) when construed literally, that their truth does not depend on our evaluative attitudes, and that we can know at least some of these truths. Such arguments are taken to support moral skepticism (according to which we cannot possess moral knowledge) or moral antirealism (for example, views that construe moral truths as functions of our evaluative attitudes, or expressivist views according to which moral judgments function to express attitudes, acceptance of norms, etc., rather than to represent moral facts, or error theoretic views according to which all moral judgments are false).

As discussed in section 2, evolutionary accounts of the origins of our capacity to be guided by moral judgments do not require any appeal to the comprehension of moral truths by our hominin ancestors, or even to the existence of such truths. Such stories require only claims about natural selection pressures having favored the development of such a capacity and tendency because of the positive effects such traits had on biological fitness (Kitcher 2006a, 176, and 2011; Joyce 2006, 131, 184; Street 2006, 127 f.; Griffiths and Wilkins 2015). Should this fact undermine our confidence in the existence of moral truth or in the possibility of moral knowledge (at least if moral truths are understood to be objective, i.e., independent of our evaluative attitudes)?

Proponents of epistemic ‘evolutionary debunking arguments’ think it should, arguing either that evolutionary considerations support moral skepticism (Joyce 2006, 2013, Forthcoming) or that they at least undermine traditional moral realism by providing a defeater for our moral beliefs if correctness for moral beliefs is construed in a realist fashion as accurate representation of objective or independent moral truths (Street 2006, 2008). (For discussion of these arguments, see Copp 2008, Kahane 2011, Enoch 2011, Skarsaune 2011, Shafer-Landau 2012, Berker 2014, Fraser 2014, FitzPatrick 2014a,b and 2017a,b, Vavova 2015, Rini 2016, Levi and Levi 2020, among many others.)

On the face of it, the mere fact that natural selection would not have ‘designed’ our moral faculties to track moral truths accurately (as it plausibly designed our perceptual faculties to track facts about medium sized objects in typical human environments) is not obviously problematic. There are, after all, lots of cases where we seem to be able to grasp genuine truths even though those truths play no role in the story of how our basic mental capacities evolved. We are able to grasp truths of quantum field theory or higher dimensional topology or, for that matter, philosophy (or so we are assuming in even engaging in this debate) even though those truths had nothing to do with why the basic mental capacities underlying these abilities evolved in our Pleistocene ancestors. Those capacities evolved in response to selection pressures in ancestral hunter-gatherer environments, and we have simply learned how to develop, train and exercise them in cultural contexts to discover truths that go far beyond any that were relevant to the evolution of those underlying capacities. Philosophers who endorse some form of moral realism have typically believed that we’ve done the same thing in grasping moral truths (see sections 2.4–2.5).

Suppose, however, that evolutionary influences not only did not design our faculties to track moral truths, but did positively shape them in ways that have pervasively conditioned the content of our moral thought and feeling, through evolved emotional dispositions or “domain specific modules” that provide us with inherited moral instincts that shape our beliefs. Debunkers have claimed that this is the case and argued that it has deep metaethical implications. Though there are a variety of formulations of such arguments, with somewhat different targets (some attacking moral knowledge itself, others seeking only to undermine moral realism by showing that it would saddle us with moral skepticism), a core argument based on the work of Sharon Street may be spelled out roughly like this:

Evolutionary Debunking Argument:

“Our system of evaluative judgments is thoroughly saturated with evolutionary influence,” because of the role natural selection played in shaping our underlying psychological dispositions (Street 2006, 114). But natural selection shaped those dispositions simply according to which variations best contributed to the biological fitness of our hominin ancestors, rather than in ways that would be expected to track independent moral truths as such, even if they existed. That is, natural selection rewarded moral belief-forming dispositions that yielded whatever moral beliefs led to behaviors that caused hunter-gatherers to out-reproduce their peers and propagate their genes more effectively, regardless of whether or not these beliefs happened accurately to represent a realm of independent moral truths. (The same would have been true for religious beliefs and theological truths: all that mattered were the relevant effects on genetic propagation, as through increased cooperation and rule following based on belief in a watchful god, assuming the religious belief-forming dispositions were under genetic control and subject to selection pressures. Theological truth or falsity was beside the point.) But since realists do not understand moral truths simply to be a function of what helped Pleistocene hunter-gatherers to maximize their reproductive output, it would be a sheer coincidence if our evolutionarily shaped moral beliefs happened to align with the moral truths, accurately representing them. And we are not justified in thinking that any such sheer coincidence has taken place. Therefore, we cannot have any justified confidence that our moral beliefs accurately represent independent moral truths of the sort posited by realists. That is, our justification for our moral beliefs would be defeated by these evolutionary considerations, at least if truth for moral beliefs consists in accurately representing independent moral facts, as realists maintain. (Epistemic internalists may deny that the facts cited above would by themselves render our moral beliefs unjustified, even on a realist model. But even they should agree that once we become aware of those facts our moral beliefs would thereby be rendered unjustified, at least given a realist model of what it would be for them to be true.) So realism saddles us with skepticism. And if such skepticism is implausible, then realism must be rejected in favor of an antirealist view (such as moral subjectivism) that would still allow for justified moral beliefs despite evolutionary influences and our awareness of them (Street 2006, 2008).

One response to this argument, on behalf of naturalistic realism, grants the claim of pervasive evolutionary influence on the contents of moral beliefs but challenges the claim that this should undermine our confidence in these beliefs. David Copp (2008), for example, has argued that on the conception of moral truths implied by his society-centered moral naturalism, it is plausible to suppose that a moral psychology shaped by natural selection in social contexts would yield moral beliefs that track moral truths at least reasonably well as a first approximation. On such a view, moral truths are grounded in moral standards having to do with codes that would enable societies to meet their basic needs (continued existence, stable cooperation among members, internal harmony and peaceful relations with other societies). Given the account of the evolution of human moral psychology sketched in section 2.3, involving the evolution of a capacity for normative guidance in connection with promoting social stability and cooperation (ultimately, of course, because of effects on genetic propagation), and further contributions of cultural evolution toward the development of moral codes fostering those same goals, many of our moral beliefs would naturally have to do with conditions for social stability and cooperation. Since on the proposed naturalistic view this is just what moral truths are about, there would thus be a tendency for our moral beliefs to have been shaped in ways that do tend to track moral truths, especially combined with continued cultural developments for correcting beliefs or attitudes that fail to contribute to these social goals.

Street (2008) has replied to this proposed way out of the problem, in part, by noting that Copp’s strategy relies on his intuitions about what the moral truths are, as reflected in his society-centered moral theory. But those are precisely the intuitions of an evolved theorist, ex hypothesi influenced by the same evolutionary factors that influenced the moral beliefs in question. So of course we can expect there to be a decent alignment between our evolutionarily shaped moral beliefs and the moral truths described by a moral theory spun by the very same evolutionarily shaped mind. Such a move, she argues, therefore cannot really help the realist. It would be different if God independently (and convincingly) revealed to us what the moral truths are, so that we could then go check our moral beliefs against them and perhaps discover that they line up pretty well; but instead, all we’re doing is comparing our moral beliefs with a purported list of moral truths yielded by a theory we find plausible precisely because it is appealing to our evolved sensibilities (though see Locke 2014 and FitzPatrick 2014b for some complications here).

Similar and even worse worries arise for a subset of non-naturalists who grant the debunkers’ claims about pervasive evolutionary influence on our moral beliefs and also insist that moral properties and facts have played no role at any point in the formation of our moral beliefs, which have instead been caused by some ‘third factor’ that happens to have brought about the desired correlation (Wielenberg 2010, Enoch 2011). One can, of course, tell a story about some such third factor: perhaps the ‘evolutionary aim’, survival and reproduction, also happens to be good, so that in giving us moral beliefs that promoted survival and reproduction evolution also happened to give us moral belief dispositions that are largely accurate (Enoch 2011). But the question is again how one is entitled to rely on moral intuitions (e.g., that survival and reproduction are good) in telling that story, even after granting that those intuitions are simply the product of ‘morally blind’ causes, i.e., causes operating entirely insensitively to moral properties and facts. There are also deeper difficulties concerning oversimplifications in such accounts (e.g., regarding the ‘evolutionary aim’) and the fact that on this approach the correlations between moral beliefs and moral truths ultimately rest on a mere accident, raising doubts about whether such accounts can really make sense of the kind of moral knowledge and understanding realists think we have (Bedke 2009, FitzPatrick 2014b).

Realists have further resources, however, which can be deployed to supplement a move such as Copp’s, in a way that blocks the above dialectical worry raised by Street. Street’s objection to Copp, after all, has teeth only if the realist has already granted the strong claims about “tremendous” and pervasive evolutionary influence “saturating” our moral beliefs across the board. It is far from clear, however, why realists should accept such strong claims to begin with. As discussed in section 2, it seems doubtful that the scientific evidence itself supports such strong claims about the etiology of ‘our’ moral beliefs. Even if there is significant evolutionary influence on the content of many of our moral beliefs, it remains possible that many of our moral beliefs are arrived at partly (or in some cases wholly) through autonomous moral reflection and reasoning, just as with our mathematical, scientific and philosophical beliefs.

Consider how a moral realist will approach the above debunking argument. It is intended to show us that realism is untenable, which of course means that this conclusion cannot just be assumed from the start. Yet if we begin the argument allowing that there may be independent moral truths, then why should we accept the initial claim about the pervasive influence of evolutionary forces on the content of our moral thinking in the first place? If there are independent moral truths, then we may plausibly have grasped many of them through autonomous exercises of our capacities for moral reflection, whereby we have come to recognize good reasons for thinking certain moral propositions to be true, by correctly grasping that certain features of actions are wrong-making, say.

For example, your belief that human trafficking is wrong is plausibly best explained by citing your reasons for holding it: you believe it’s wrong for the reasons you give, such as the fact that it causes tremendous suffering and deprivation, violates the basic dignity and rights of its victims, and so on. From a realist perspective, these features you cite in giving your reasons for the belief are in fact wrong-making features of human trafficking, i.e., features that make trafficking wrong and therefore make true the moral proposition that human trafficking is wrong. On this picture, you therefore believe that trafficking is wrong because it is wrong and you’ve come to recognize the moral fact that it is wrong by recognizing the reasons why it is wrong (FitzPatrick 2016).

Unless realism has already been rejected for other reasons, then, this picture is an open possibility at the start of the debate, which means that the realist is entitled to hold that many of our moral beliefs are in fact not merely caused by evolutionary and other ‘morally blind’ influences, but are instead well-grounded responses to moral reality. That is, the realist need never grant the debunker’s strong claims to the effect that our moral beliefs across the board are saturated with evolutionary influence (see section 2). Perhaps some are and some aren’t, and the proportions will depend on the extent to which we’ve successfully exercised autonomous reflection in arriving at our moral beliefs, which is a wide open question. If there are enough autonomous beliefs in the mix, and we can identify them, then the rest of the argument will not go through (FitzPatrick 2014a,b; 2016, 2017a,b). [ 12 ]

The debunking argument would be strengthened if we had good reason to be skeptical about autonomous moral reflection. In this vein, Street claims that whatever moral reflection and reasoning we engage in is limited merely to assessing “thoroughly contaminated” evaluative beliefs using “tools of rational reflection [that are] equally contaminated” (Street 2006: 124). The problem, however, is that this claim is based upon the very premise in question: the tools of reflection are allegedly thoroughly contaminated because of the “tremendous” evolutionary influence on the content of “our” moral judgments across the board; yet our question is why we should believe the latter in the first place. Until we are given independent reason to discount the power of moral reflection so radically, treating it as nothing more than using some rotten apples to judge other rotten apples, we seem to have little reason to dismiss the possibility of autonomous moral reflection, and therefore little reason to accept the initial claim of pervasive “saturation” of our moral beliefs with evolutionary influence.

Street actually casts her argument in terms of a “Darwinian dilemma” for realists, which centers around the following question: what is the relation between the evolutionary shaping of moral judgments and the independent moral truths posited by realists? (Street 2006, 109). As already noted, the best scientific accounts suggest that there would be no special relation here, even if such moral truths existed. But if there is no special relation between this evolutionary shaping and independent moral truths, then we would have no reason to trust our moral beliefs, which are as likely to be off-track as on-track, leading to moral skepticism. So the realist seems to face a dilemma : reject the best available science or lose all justification for our moral beliefs.

As brought out above, one way out of the dilemma for a realist is simply to deny that the evolutionary influence on the content of our moral beliefs is as pervasive as Street claims. The realist can grant that where such influence does exist we cannot assume that it would have pushed our beliefs toward moral truth: it may accidentally have done so in some cases (e.g., influencing us to think we have obligations to care for our children) and it might have been distorting in others (e.g., influencing us to downplay obligations to those who do not belong to our in-group). But this is not a problem if we also have a culturally developed capacity for autonomous moral reflection and reasoning that allows us to attain moral knowledge despite the presence of some unreliable influences. Realists will claim that we don’t need natural selection to have given us moral beliefs that track moral truths, any more than we need this in science or philosophy: all we need is for natural selection to have given us faculties that we can develop, train and use in ways that reliably track moral truths, and enough freedom from evolutionarily given instincts that we can so exercise those faculties.

Finally, Street challenges the realist to specify what faculty or capacity might ground our capacity to arrive at independent moral truths, how the former evolved, and how the latter could plausibly have arisen as a byproduct of it. She claims that there is no plausible story to be told here, since the capacity to grasp independent moral truths would have to be “a highly specialized, sophisticated capacity” akin to the human eye, and no such entity could plausibly emerge “as the purely incidental byproduct of some unrelated capacity that was selected for on other grounds entirely” (Street 2006, 142–43). But the realist’s story needn’t take that form. The claim will be just that our capacity to grasp moral truths—like our capacity to grasp philosophical truths about metaphysical necessity, say—is simply a byproduct of our general capacities for critical reasoning, combined with the evolved capacity for forming and employing normative concepts in our thinking and decision-making.

A related but somewhat different debunking argument focuses on the origins of moral concepts (Joyce 2006, chap. 6). It begins with the claim that we have a complete non -moral genealogy of our moral beliefs—a complete explanation of how we’ve come to believe what we do, which does not require any appeal to moral truths . Instead, we explain the origins of our moral concepts—such as fairness, justice, and guilt—in evolutionary terms, recalling that natural selection would have rewarded genetic propagation, not the tracking of moral truths, in shaping them; and then we explain our beliefs employing those moral concepts in familiar sociological and psychological terms. The claim is then that the existence of such a non-moral geneaology of moral beliefs makes the notion of moral truths “explanatorily superfluous”—just as truths about witches are explanatorily superfluous given a complete genealogy of beliefs about witches that does not involve any appeal to truths about witches. And if moral truths are explanatorily superfluous, then we should not posit them, any more than we posit truths about witches: we should remain agnostic about moral truth and give up any claims to moral knowledge. In other words, evolutionary biology leads to moral skepticism.

The critical questions about this argument parallel those raised about the previous one. Even if it is granted that crude versions of our concepts of fairness or guilt originated through evolutionary processes in our hominin ancestors, independently of any connection to moral truths, it remains possible that through cultural evolution we have developed refined conceptions of fairness or guilt that can be employed in epistemically respectable ways (FitzPatrick 2014a). Regardless of how and why the concept of fairness originated, why should we doubt that we can today use a refined conception of fairness to state moral truths, such as the truth that race-based voting laws are unfair and wrong? If there are grounds of skepticism about this they would have to lie in reasons to doubt the soundness of our first-order moral arguments about fairness, rather than in claims about how and why a crude version of the concept first arose (Nagel 1997).

Absent such doubts, it’s not clear why the mere fact of historical evolutionary influence should undermine our confidence in our moral claims. To draw an analogy, should a theist give up her belief just because crude, ancestral forms of religious belief can be causally explained without appeal to theological facts? Perhaps she will if she finds no good reasons for her own belief, and concludes that it is to be explained along similar lines. But if she has reflected on the matter and been persuaded by a “cosmological argument from fine tuning,” for example, then it seems she might reasonably maintain her belief, taking her employment of the concept of a deity to be epistemically legitimate despite the fact that other employments are subject to debunking evolutionary, sociological and psychological explanations.

In general, the worry about Joyce’s debunking argument is similar to the worry about Street’s: unless we start out already assuming (against the realist) that there are no knowable moral truths, it is hard to see why we should accept Joyce’s premise that we possess a complete non -moral geneaology of moral judgment, and hence that it is explanatorily superfluous to posit moral truths. Whether or not the non-moral geneaology is complete is precisely what is in question in ongoing metaethical debates: realists, who posit knowable moral truths, can reasonably hold that the correct explanation for at least many of our moral beliefs does appeal to moral truths or facts that we have grasped, while anti-realists, who deny the existence of such truths, claim that the correct explanation for all of our moral beliefs involves no such appeal. The issue remains controversial. So unless one has independently settled that issue against realism, one is unlikely to accept the premise that there is a complete non-moral genealogy of our moral beliefs: there may well be a partial non-moral genealogy, for the sorts of reasons Joyce gives, but it will be complete only if none of our moral beliefs are the result of our having grasped moral truths; and this negative claim will be very unlikely if there are in fact knowable moral truths (since we would plausibly have grasped some of them, and they would thus figure into the explanation of some of our moral beliefs). We should therefore feel compelled to grant Joyce’s premise that there is such a complete non-moral genealogy only if we have already given up on the idea of knowable moral truths. But that makes it hard to see how the argument as a whole can be used to persuade anyone who doesn’t already accept its conclusion.

It is worth noting that the appeal to evolution to support general skeptical worries about ethics is not in fact new: it goes all the back to Darwin himself. Consider the following provocative, fanciful reflection (later echoed closely by E.O. Wilson 1978, 204–206), which at least suggests a skeptical argument closely related to the debunking arguments examined above:

It may be well first to premise that I do not wish to maintain that any strictly social animal, if its intellectual faculties were to become as active and as highly developed as in man, would acquire exactly the same moral sense as ours. In the same manner as various animals have some sense of beauty, though they admire widely different objects, so they might have a sense of right and wrong, though led by it to follow widely different lines of conduct. If, for instance, to take an extreme case, men were reared under precisely the same conditions as hive-bees, there can hardly be a doubt that our unmarried females would, like the worker-bees, think it a sacred duty to kill their brothers, and mothers would strive to kill their fertile daughters; and no one would think of interfering. Nevertheless the bee, or any other social animal, would in our supposed case gain, as it appears to me, some feeling of right and wrong, or a conscience (Darwin 1871, 73).

The argument at least suggested by this passage is that our moral sense, which generates our moral beliefs, has the shape and content it has because of the contingencies of human ecology; had creatures with a very different ecology, such as bees, come to be rational, they would thus have developed a very different moral sense suitable to their ecology. But then which of these very different moral senses could be expected reliably to track moral truths (if they exist)? The answer seems to be: neither (unless we simply relativize moral truths to various possible ecologies, taking such truths to reduce to facts about effective genetic propagation—though as we saw in section 3, such a move has little moral plausibility). For moral senses are contingent products of particular ecologies in a way that cannot be expected to track independent and stable moral truths. We and the hypothetical rational bees will thus have very different moral outlooks, each of which is explicable in terms of our respective ecologies and will seem quite natural to those who occupy the relevant ecology (while the other’s outlook will seem bizarre), but neither of which seems to have any claim to be a reliable guide to moral truth (as usually conceived). This imaginary exercise in perspective thus seems to support moral skepticism: the very idea of independent, stable moral truths will seem suspect (playing no role in the explanation of the origins of various possible moral senses), and our confidence that our moral sense would track them in any case will seem unwarranted.

What such an argument overlooks, however, is precisely the factor of autonomous moral reflection that the bees’ imagined rationality would bring with it (see sections 2.4–2.5, and McDowell 1995). True, we might expect relatively unreflective and tradition-bound bees to speak of “sacred duties” to kill brothers or fertile daughters, in a way that lines up with the relevant genetic relations that figured into the evolution of their given moral senses. But we could equally expect more reflective bees (the buzzing philosophers among them) to raise the question whether they really had good reason to do everything that their evolution has disposed them to do in the service of maximizing their genetic propagation. These more philosophical bees might consider the possibility that some potential goods of bee life, in the context of ongoing innovations in rational bee culture, might be available to them if they resisted certain impulses and acted differently; and this might lead to the development of at least partly autonomous moral norms, and hence moral senses that are a complex mixture of inherited dispositions and rational judgment.

If bees became rational, then, there is no reason to suppose that their moral sensibilities would simply reflect their ecology any more than human moral sensibilities simply reflect human ecology: to the extent that they are really rational, we should expect some autonomous reflection, and perhaps even significant overlap with autonomous human moral reflection, as we both strive for something beyond the merely biologically useful (FitzPatrick 2000, 355–56, and 2017b). This is not to suggest, of course, that moral truths or objective moral norms, if they exist, will be exactly the same for human life and for rational bee life, or for actual human life and human life imagined under vastly different ecological circumstances. On any plausible view of morality, there will be significant variation in moral principles and/or their applications where there is significant variation in the basic facts of life. Just as we could never live just like bees, bees could never live just like humans, and no reasonable morality would demand such a thing. Even a realist, then, will grant a significant degree of cross-species moral relativism (or counterfactual moral relativism for deeply different courses of human evolution). But it needn’t be the extreme and implausible relativism linking true moral standards simply and directly to ecology, and whatever moral truths might obtain for each species might well be accessible to members of each species through autonomous moral reflection, with at least some points of convergence.

Before leaving the topic of evolutionary debunking arguments, it should be noted that in addition to the general arguments considered above, which are aimed at debunking morality (or in Street’s case, debunking a realist construal of morality) as a whole , there are also evolutionary debunking arguments meant instead just to target a selected range of moral beliefs as epistemically suspect. Such selective debunking arguments may be deployed by moral realists who reject general debunking arguments in this domain but nonetheless wish to use similar tactics to discredit certain kinds of moral belief as part of advancing their own normative ethical project. They might argue, for example, that while the deontological beliefs held by their opponents can be successfully debunked by appeal to evolutionary considerations, their own utilitarian ethical beliefs are immune from such debunking, stemming from autonomous rational reflection rather than from evolved psychological modules shaped by the distorting influences of natural selection.

This is the strategy adopted by Katarzyna de Lazari-Radek and Peter Singer (2014) in an effort to support Sidgwick’s principle of Universal Benevolence, i.e., impartial utilitarianism. That principle is inconsistent not only with moral egoism but with any moral stance that incorporates limited forms of partiality (such as special duties to family and friends even when not utility-maximizing, or constraints against taking certain means when promoting utility, or moral permissions to favor oneself or loved ones to some degree over strangers). So in order to discredit such competing moral views, they claim that one can tell debunking evolutionary stories to ‘explain away’ these non-utilitarian moral beliefs as unreliable products of distorting evolutionary influences: people believe such things only because natural selection shaped human moral psychology in the direction of selfishness and at best parochial altruism, for Darwinian reasons having nothing to do with moral truth. Then, in effect, they treat the possibility of telling such debunking evolutionary stories as sufficient to undermine epistemic justification for the targeted moral beliefs. At the same time, however, they maintain that their own favored ethical beliefs, involving strict impartiality, are invulnerable to any similar treatment, so that we can remain confident in the rationality of utilitarian morality.

There are reasons to doubt whether this sort of theoretically ambitious but selective evolutionary debunking strategy is a viable or stable one (Kahane 2011 and 2014, Rini 2016, FitzPatrick 2017a). A natural worry is that if such debunking arguments really worked against opponents of utilitarianism in the manner suggested, then similar arguments could equally be deployed against utilitarianism if we play by the same rules. The selective debunking arguments used by de Lazari-Radek and Singer give a great deal of negative epistemic weight to the mere existence of possible debunking explanations which, if true , would clearly pose a problem for the targeted beliefs (even though it remains a wide open question whether such explanatory stories are in fact true). That is, they give great weight to the mere ability to tell a plausible debunking story according to which non-utilitarian moral beliefs would turn out to be problematically rooted in ‘contaminated starting points’ (psychological dispositions resulting from morally blind evolutionary forces) that have merely been refined over time by culturally conditioned causal influences operating equally blindly to moral truths. This raises problems for them, however, because one can easiliy enough come up with similar debunking stories about utilitarian beliefs, according to which they would equally turn out to be problematically shaped by morally-blind evolutionary forces that contaminated the starting points.

Here is just one way such a story could go (FitzPatrick 2017a). Recall the possibility discussed in sub-sections 2.2 and 2.3, that in early ancestral environments involving mostly small in-group interactions, where there were relatively few opportunities for ‘wasting’ altruistic tendencies on outsiders, natural selection gave rise to some fairly indiscriminate dispositions involving sympathy and altruism. (Or again, recall the adaptive plasticity model from Buchanan and Powell 2018, discussed in section 3.4, which posits environmentally sensitive inclusivist tendencies as part of evolved human psychology.) As long as such indiscriminate altruism contributed more to fitness in that environment than it detracted from it through occasional ‘misfirings’ of such sentiments and behaviors directed at non-cooperators, it could very well have evolved as a simple fitness-enhancing mechanism (Kitcher 2006b). Someone who wishes to debunk impartial utilitarianism might then tell a story according to which the utilitarian’s impartial sympathy and concern is nothing but an extension of this evolved psychological trait, whereby it is systematically ‘misfiring’ (from a biological point of view) in our current environment. More precisely, the story would be that current utilitarian beliefs represent a cultural refinement of such evolved tendencies via an application of reasoning, such as the consistency reasoning utilitarians employ in arguing for an “expanding circle” of moral concern and an increasingly impartial altruism. The debunker will claim that however rational such inferential steps may be in themselves, they are still just operating on certain moral starting points that are ‘contaminated’ by evolutionary influence: namely, deeply ingrained moral intuitions about the intrinsic badness of suffering wherever it occurs, or the goodness of pleasure, which trace back to evolved psychological dispositions to recoil at suffering and injury, and to feel sympathy for others. Basic utilitarian moral intuitions, no less than non-utilitarian intuitions, may ultimately be nothing but illusions foisted on us by our evolutionary history, rooted in contaminated starting points (Ruse 2006). In both cases, proponents of the moral views in question have moved well beyond the original evolved dispositions, through culturally-developed reasoning that has refined them in various ways. But if this doesn’t save non-utilitarian moral beliefs given the debunking story about the contaminated starting points, then it won’t save utilitarian moral beliefs either.

Now de Lazari-Radek and Singer might reasonably wish to counter such debunking attacks by claiming that even if there are such evolutionary influences at the root of their intuitions about the badness of suffering or the propriety of impartial altruism, the reflection and reasoning that has taken place over centuries of sophisticated moral inquiry has not merely provided for more consistent applications of evolutionarily contaminated dispositions: it has instead amounted to the intellectual discovery of good reasons to believe the contents of utilitarian moral claims to be true . This philosophical possibility certainly remains on the table and hasn’t been shown not to obtain simply because an aspiring debunker can tell a debunking story according to which it doesn’t. And such a reply would indeed be a plausible response to the debunker, making precisely the point emphasized earlier in section 4.1, in responding to general debunking arguments. The problem, however, is that if they are entitled to make this response to the debunker on behalf of utilitarian moral beliefs, then so are their opponents on behalf of non-utilitarian moral beliefs: what’s good for the utilitarian goose is good for the non-utilitarian gander.

In other words, to escape evolutionary debunking themselves, it seems that de Lazari-Radek and Singer will have to allow that the mere existence of a possible evolutionary debunking explanation for a set of moral beliefs does not undermine epistemic justification for them. It matters whether or not that story is actually the correct explanatory story, including its claim that the beliefs in question are exhaustively accounted for simply in terms of the morally-blind, extraneous causes in question, rather than partly through rational grasp of good reasons for believing their contents to be true; and merely being able to tell a debunking story does not establish such a strong claim. Once this is recognized, however, the same principle applies to just the sorts of debunking arguments they have deployed against non-utilitarians, who can thus avoid them in the same way.

One or more of the debunking stories could, of course, still turn out to be true, and they do need to be taken seriously as possibilities. The critical points raised here are just, first, that it is unclear whether debunking arguments really have compelling force against those who haven’t already independently rejected the positions being targeted (showing them that their beliefs are really bunk); and second, that it may be hazardous for those who reject general evolutionary debunking arguments in ethics to attempt to use similar arguments selectively against competing normative ethical views. Such potential explanations could, however, still play a supporting role within a broader set of moral arguments, contributing a possible theory of error helping to explain why some people may believe certain moral claims or theories even though they are false.

A less ambitious claim made by some antirealists is that the account in section 2.3 of the origins of our capacity for normative guidance at least lends support to or fits naturally with an expressivist metaethical view—the view that moral judgments do not even purport to state moral facts, but instead express non-cognitive states such as attitudes or acceptance of certain norms, etc. (Gibbard 1990; Kitcher 2006a). Suppose the human capacity for normative guidance is indeed an adaptation that evolved in connection with social coordination, cooperation and stability. This capacity involves being in the state of accepting a norm , which we should thus expect to be a standard part of human moral psychology and its capacity for “linguistically infused motivation” (Gibbard 1990, 55). This may lend support to a norm-expressivist approach to normative judgment, insofar as such an approach focuses precisely on the notion of accepting a norm, and the evolutionary story provides good reason to suppose that accepting a norm is a “natural, biological phenomenon” (61).

It is less clear, however, whether anything stronger than this can be said. Suppose it’s true that we evolved a capacity and tendency for normative guidance because of the coordinating social function achieved by the expression of norm acceptance. Not only does this leave open what we now use that capacity to do, but it even leaves open what exactly our ancestors did with it. One possibility is that the activity they were engaged with was non-cognitive : they were merely expressing non-cognitive states comprising attitudes and states of norm acceptance. Kitcher (2006a) suggests that this is the metaethical picture best supported by the evolutionary story. But Joyce (2006, 175–76) has disputed this. Even granting that the biological function of moral judgment is social coordination, the linguistic function of moral judgments could go either way: it may be that the biological function was carried out through non-cognitive expressions of norm acceptance, but it may equally instead be that it was carried out through cognitive judgments involving claims to objective validity . Indeed, the social function might be all the better served if those making moral judgments firmly believe in objective values and assert those beliefs, even if they are in fact making a projective error in doing so, as error theorists claim. Compare: even if religious belief has a biological function (e.g., reducing anxiety), it wouldn’t follow that religious assertions are non-cognitive and so aren’t really assertions, and the story might be more plausible if it is assumed that they are genuine assertions (Joyce 2006, 176, 208; Ruse 2006).

Thus, although the evolutionary story fits naturally with a merely non-cognitivist metaethical view, it may fit equally well with a cognitivist view. If one rejects the existence of moral truths, the latter would then lead to an error theory (Mackie 1977). But as discussed in section 4.1, it is far from clear how much support evolutionary biology itself lends to moral anti-realism or irrealism. It is consistent with plausible evolutionary stories that although our capacities for normative guidance originally evolved for reasons that had nothing to do with moral truths as such, we now regularly employ them to deliberate about and to communicate moral truths. So all three metaethical views discussed here—expressivism, error theory and moral realism—remain on the table.

  • Alexander, R., 1987, The Biology of Moral Systems , New York: Aldine de Gruyter.
  • Appiah, K.A., 2008, Experiments in Ethics , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Axelrod, R., 1984, The Evolution of Cooperation , New York: Basic Books.
  • –––, 2006, “Biology to Ethics: An Evolutionist’s View of Human Nature,” in Boniolo, G. and De Anna, G., Evolutionary Ethics and Contemporary Biology , pp. 141–58.
  • Bedke, M., 2009, “Intuitive Non-Naturalism Meets Cosmic Coincidence,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly , 90: 188–209.
  • Berker, S., 2009, “The Normative Insignificance of Neuroscience,” Philosophy and Public Affairs , 37: 293–329.
  • –––, 2014, “Does Evolutionary Psychology Show that Normativity is Mind-Dependent?” in J. D’Arms and D. Jacobson (eds.), Moral Psychology and Human Agency: Essays on the New Science of Ethics , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Boniolo, G. and De Anna, G., 2006, Evolutionary Ethics and Contemporary Biology , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Brosnan, R. and de Waal, F., 2014, “Evolution of Responses to (Un)fairness,” Science , 346(6207): 1251776.
  • Buchanan, A. and Powell, R., 2015, “The Limits of Evolutionary Explanations of Morality and Their Implications for Moral Progress,” Ethics , 126(1): 37–67.
  • –––, 2018, The Evolution of Moral Progress: A Biocultural Theory , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2019, “Precis of The Evolution of Moral Progress: A Biocultural Theory ,” Analyse & Kritik , 41(2): 183–193.
  • Buchanan, A., 2020, Our Moral Fate: Evolution and the Escape from Tribalism , Cambridge: MIT Press.
  • Buller, D., 2005, Evolutionary Psychology and the Persistent Quest for Human Nature , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Buss, D.M., 2005, The Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology , Hoboken: Wiley.
  • Casebeer, W., 2003, Natural Ethical Facts: Evolution, Connectionism, and Moral Cognition , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Clarke-Doane, J., 2012, “Morality and Mathematics: The Evolutionary Challenge,” Ethics , 122: 313–40.
  • –––, 2014, “Moral Epistemology: The Mathematics Analogy,” Noûs , 48(2): 238–255.
  • Copp, D., 2008, “Darwinian Skepticism about Moral Realism,” Philosophical Issues 18: 186–206.
  • Cosmides, L. and Tooby, J., 2008, “Can a General Deontic Logic Capture the Facts of Human Moral Reasoning?” in W. Sinnott-Armstrong (ed.), Moral Psychology , Vol. 1.
  • Dancy, J., 2014, “Intuition and Emotion,” Ethics , 124(4): 787–812.
  • Darwin, C., 1859, The Origin of Species , London: John Murray.
  • –––, 1871, The Descent of Man , and Selection in Relation to Sex , London: John Murray.
  • Dawkins, R., 1982, The Extended Phenotype , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 1989, The Selfish Gene , 2 nd edition, expanded, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2006, The God Delusion , New York: Houghton Mifflin.
  • de Lazari-Radek, K. and Singer, P., 2014, The Point of View of the Universe , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • de Waal, F., 1996, Good Natured: The Origins of Right and Wrong in Humans and Other Animals , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 2006, Primates and Philosophers , Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Diamond, J., 1992, The Third Chimpanzee: The Evolution and Future of the Human Animal , New York: Harper Collins.
  • Downes, S., 2009, “The Basic Components of the Human Mind Were Not Solidified During the Pleistocene Epoch,” in F. Ayala and R. Arp eds., Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Biology, Wiley-Blackwell, 243-252.
  • Engelmann, J., Clift, J., Herrmann, E.,and Tomasello, M., 2017, “Social Disappointment Explains Chimpanzees’ Behavior in the Inequity Aversion Task,” Proc. R. Soc. B 284: 20171502. http://dx.doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2017.1502.
  • Enoch, D., 2011, Taking Morality Seriously: A Defense of Robust Realism , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • FitzPatrick, W.J., 2000, Teleology and the Norms of Nature , New York: Garland.
  • –––, 2007, Review of Boniolo, G. and De Anna, G., eds., Evolutionary Ethics and Contemporary Biology , in Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews : 2007.04.02. [ Available online ].
  • –––, 2012, Review of Philip Kitcher, The Ethical Project , Ethics , 123(1): 167–74.
  • –––, 2014a, “Debunking Evolutionary Debunking of Ethical Realism,” Philosophical Studies , doi:10.1007/s11098-014-0295-y
  • –––, 2014b, “Why There is No Darwinian Dilemma for Ethical Realism,” in M. Bergmann and P. Kain (eds.), Challenges to Moral and Religious Belief: Disagreement and Evolution , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2016, “Scientific Naturalism and the Explanation of Moral Beliefs: Challenging Evolutionary Debunking,” in K. Clark ed., The Blackwell Companion to Naturalism , Wiley Blackwell.
  • –––, 2017a, “Human Altruism, Evolution and Moral Philosophy,” Royal Society Open Science 4: 170441 , doi:10.1098/rsos.170441
  • –––, 2017b, “Why Darwinism Does Not Debunk Objective Morality,” in M. Ruse and R.J. Richards (eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of Evolutionary Ethics , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 2018, “Cognitive Science and Moral Philosophy: Challenging Scientistic Overreach,” in J. de Ritter, R. Peels, and R. van Woudenberg (eds.), Scientism: Prospects and Problems , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Fodor, J., 1998, “The Trouble with Psychological Darwinism,” London Review of Books , 20(2): 11–13.
  • –––, 2000, The Mind Doesn’t Work That Way: The Scope and Limits of Computational Psychology , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Foot, P., 2001, Natural Goodness , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Fraser, B.J., 2014, “Evolutionary Debunking Arguments and the Reliability of Moral Cognition,” Philosophical Studies , 168: 457–473.
  • Gibbard, A., 1990, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Glover, J., 2000, Humanity: A Moral History of the 20 th Century , New Haven: Yale University Press.
  • Gould, S.J., 1997a, “Darwinian Fundamentalism,” New York Review of Books , 44(10): 34–7.
  • –––, 1997b, “Evolutionary Psychology: An Exchange,” New York Review of Books , 44(15): 55–8.
  • Gould, S.J. and Lewontin, R.C., 1979, “The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: A Critique of the Adaptationist Programme,” Proceedings of the Royal Society: Biological Sciences , 205: 581–98.
  • Greene, J.D., 2003, “From Neural ‘Is’ to Moral ‘Ought’: What are the Moral Implications of Neuroscientific Moral Psychology?”, Nature Neuroscience Reviews , 4: 847–50.
  • –––, 2008, “The Secret Joke of Kant’s Soul,” in W. Sinnott-Armstrong (ed.), Moral Psychology , Volume 3, pp. 35–80.
  • Griffiths, P. and J. Wilkins, 2015, “When Do Evolutionary Explanations of Belief Debunk Belief?” in P. Sloan (ed.), Darwin in the 21st Century: Nature, Humanity and God , Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame University Press.
  • Haidt, J., 2001, “The Emotional Dog and Its Rational Tail: A Social Intuitionist Approach to Moral Judgment,” Psychological Review , 108(4): 814–34.
  • –––, 2003, “The Emotional Dog Learns New Tricks: A Reply to Pizarro and Bloom (2003),” Psychological Review , 110(1): 197–98.
  • Hamilton, W.D., 1964, “The Genetical Evolution of Social Behavior,” I and II, Journal of Theoretical Biology , 7: 1–52.
  • Holldobler, B and Wilson, E.O., 2008, The Superorganism: The Beauty, Elegance, and Strangeness of Insect Societies , New York: Norton and Company.
  • Huemer, M., 2016, “A Liberal Realist Answer to Debunking Skeptics: The Empirical Case for Realism,” Philosophical Studies , 173: 1983–2010.
  • Joyce, R., 2006, The Evolution of Morality , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • –––, 2013, “Irrealism and the Genealogy of Morals,” Ratio , 26(4): 351–72.
  • –––, Forthcoming, “Evolution, Truth-Tracking, and Moral Skepticism,” in B. Reichardt (ed.), Problems of Goodness , Bonn: Bernstein Verlag.
  • Kahane, G., 2011, “Evolutionary Debunking Arguments,” Nous , 45(1): 103–125.
  • –––, 2014, “Ethics and Impartiality,” Ethics , 124 (January): 327–341.
  • Kamm, F., 1998, “Moral Intuitions, Cognitive Psychology, and the Harming-versus-Not-Aiding Distinction,” Ethics , 108 (April): 463–488.
  • –––, 2007, Intricate Ethics: Rights, Responsibilities, and Permissible Harm , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Katz, L.D. (ed.), 2000, Evolutionary Origins of Morality: Cross Disciplinary Perspectives , Exeter: Imprint Academic.
  • Kitcher, P., 1985, Vaulting Ambition , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • –––, 1993, “The Evolution of Human Altruism,” Journal of Philosophy , 90(10): 497–516.
  • –––, 1994, “Four Ways of ‘Biologizing’ Ethics,” in E. Sober (ed.), Conceptual Issues in Evolutionary Ethics , pp. 439–50.
  • –––, 2006a, “Biology and Ethics,” in Copp, D. ed., The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory , Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 163–85.
  • –––, 2006b, “Between Fragile Altruism and Morality: Evolution and the Emergence of Normative Guidance,” in G. Boniolo and G. De Anna (eds.), Evolutionary Ethics and Contemporary Biology , pp. 159–77.
  • –––, 2006c, “Ethics and Evolution: How to Get Here from There,” in F. de Waal, Primates and Philosophers , pp. 120–39.
  • –––, 2011, The Ethical Project , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Knobe, J. and Leiter, B., 2007, “The Case for Nietzschean Moral Psychology,” in Nietzsche and Morality , B. Leiter & N. Sinhababu (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Korsgaard, C., 2006, “Morality and the Distinctiveness of Human Action,” in de Waal, Primates and Philosophers , pp. 98–119.
  • Leiter, B., 2007, “Nietzsche’s Theory of the Will,” Philosopher’s Imprint , 7(7): 1–15.
  • Levy, A. and Levy, Y., 2020, “Evolutionary Debunking Arguments Meet Evolutionary Science,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , 100(3): 491–509.
  • Locke, D., 2014, “Darwinian Normative Skepticism,” in M. Bergmann and P. Kain (eds.), Challenges to Moral and Religious Belief: Disagreement and Evolution , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Lott, M., 2012, “Have Elephant Seals Refuted Aristotle? Nature, Function and Moral Goodness,” Journal of Moral Philosophy , 9: 1–23.
  • Machery, E. and R. Mallon, 2010, “Evolution of Morality,” in J. Doris (ed.), The Moral Psychology Handbook , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Maynard Smith, J., 1982, Evolution and the Theory of Games , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • McDowell, J., 1995, “Two Sorts of Naturalism,” in R. Hursthouse, G. Lawrence, and W. Quinn (eds.), Virtues and Reasons , Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 149–80.
  • Mele, A., 2008, “Free Will: Action Theory Meets Neuroscience,” in Lumer, C., ed., Intentionality, Deliberation and Autonomy: The Action-Theoretic Basis of Practical Philosophy , Burlington: Ashgate.
  • Mikhail, J., 2011, Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls’ Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Moosavi, P., 2019, “From Biological Functions to Natural Goodness,” Philosopher’s Imprint , 19(51).
  • Nagel, T., 1979, “Ethics Without Biology”, in Mortal Questions , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 142–46.
  • –––, 1997, The Last Word , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Nichols, Shaun, 2004, Sentimental Rules: On the Natural Foundations of Moral Judgment , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Pinker, S., 1997a, “Evolutionary Psychology: An Exchange,” New York Review of Books 44(15): 55–8.
  • –––, 1997b, How the Mind Works , New York: Norton.
  • –––, 2008, “The Moral Instinct,” The New York Times Magazine , January 13: 32–58.
  • Pizarro, D. and Bloom, P., 2003, “The Intelligence of the Moral Intuitions: Comments on Haidt (2001),” Psychological Review , 110(1): 193–96.
  • Prinz, J., 2008, “Is Morality Innate?”, in Sinnott-Armstrong, W., Moral Psychology , 1: 367-406.
  • Rachels, J., 1990, Created From Animals: The Moral Implications of Darwinism , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Railton, P., 2014, “The Affective Dog and its Rational Tale: Intuition and Attunement,” Ethics , 124(4): 813–859.
  • Rini, R., 2016, “Debunking Debunking: A Regress Challenge for Psychological Threats to Moral Judgment,” Philosophical Studies , 173(3): 675–697.
  • Rosati, C., 1995, “Naturalism, Normativity, and the Open Question Argument,” Noûs , 29(1): 46–70.
  • Rosenberg, A., 2006, “Will Genomics Do More for Metaphysics than Locke?”, in G. Boniolo and G. De Anna (eds.), Evolutionary Ethics and Contemporary Biology , pp. 178–98.
  • Rottschaefer, W., 1998, The Biology and Psychology of Moral Agency , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Ruse, M., 1988, “Evolutionary Ethics: Healthy Prospect or Last Infirmity?”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy (Supplement), 14: 27–73.
  • –––, 2006, “Is Darwinian Metaethics Possible (And If It Is, Is It Well Taken)?”, in G. Boniolo and G. De Anna (eds.), Evolutionary Ethics and Contemporary Biology , pp. 13–26.
  • Schafer, K., 2010, “Evolution and Normative Skepticism,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy , 88: 471–88.
  • Shafer-Landau, R., 2012, “Evolutionary Debunking, Moral Realism and Moral Knowledge,” Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy , 7(1): 1–37.
  • Singer, P., 2005, “Ethics and Intuitions,” Journal of Ethics , 9: 331–52.
  • Sinnott-Armstrong, W., 2005, “Moral Intuitionism Meets Empirical Psychology,” in T. Horgan and M. Timmons (eds.), Metaethics After Moore , Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 339–66.
  • ––– (ed.), 2008, Moral Psychology , Vol. 1: The Evolution of Morality: Adaptations and Innateness , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • ––– (ed.), 2008a, Moral Psychology , Vol. 2: The Cognitive Science of Morality: Intuition and Diversity , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • ––– (ed.), 2008b, Moral Psychology , Vol. 3: The Neuroscience of Morality: Emotion, Brain Disorders, and Development , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Skarsaune, K.O., 2011, “Darwin and Moral Realism: Survival of the Iffiest,” Philosophical Studies , 152: 229–243.
  • Sober, E. (ed.), 1994, Conceptual Issues in Evolutionary Ethics , 2 nd ed., Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Sober, E. and Wilson, D.S., 1998, Unto Others: The Evolution and Psychology of Unselfish Behavior , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Sommers, T., and Rosenberg, A., 2003, “Darwin’s Nihilistic Idea: Evolution and the Meaninglessness of Life,” Biology and Philosophy , 18: 653–68.
  • Spencer, H., 1879, The Data of Ethics , New York: Thomas Y. Crowell & Company.
  • Street, S., 2006, “A Darwinian Dilemma for Realist Theories of Value,” Philosophical Studies , 127: 109–66.
  • –––, 2008, “Reply to Copp: Naturalism, Normativity, and the Varieties of Realism Worth Worrying About,” Philosophical Issues , 18: 207–28.
  • Starratt, V. and Shackelford, T., 2009, “The Basic Components of the Human Mind Were Solidified During the Pleistocene Epoch,” in F. Ayala and R. Arp eds., Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Biology, Wiley-Blackwell, 231-242.
  • Sterelny, K. and Fraser, B, 2016, “Evolution and Moral Realism,” Brit. J. Phil. Sci 68 (2017), 981–1006.
  • Thompson, M., 1998, “The Representation of Life,” in Hursthouse, R., Lawrence, G., and Quinn, W., eds., Virtues and Reasons , Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 247–96.
  • –––, 2008, Life and Action , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Thomson, J., 1985, “The Trolley Problem,” The Yale Law Journal , 94: 1395–1415.
  • Tooby, J. and Cosmides, L, 2005, “Conceptual Foundations of Evolutionary Psychology,” in D. Buss (ed.), The Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology , pp. 5–67.
  • Trivers, R., 1971, “The Evolution of Reciprocal Altruism,” Quarterly Review of Biology , 46: 35–57.
  • Vavova, K., 2015, “Evolutionary Debunking of Moral Realism,” Philosophy Compass , 10(2): 104–116.
  • Wheatley, T. and Haidt, J., 2005, “Hypnotically Induced Disgust Makes Moral Judgments More Severe,” Psychological Science , 16: 780–84.
  • Wielenberg, E., 2010, “On the Evolutionary Debunking of Morality,” Ethics , 120: 441–64.
  • Wilson, E.O., 1975, Sociobiology: The New Synthesis , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 1978, On Human Nature , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 1998, “The Biological Basis of Morality,” The Atlantic Monthly (April): 53–70.
  • Wilson, E.O. and Ruse, M., 1986, “Moral Philosophy as Applied Science,” Philosophy , 61: 173–92.
  • Wilson, J.Q., 1993, The Moral Sense , New York: The Free Press.
  • Wrangham, R., 1987, “The Evolution of Social Structure,” in B. Smuts, et al. (eds.), Primate Societies , Chicago: Chicago University Press, pp. 282–96.
  • Wright, R., 1994, The Moral Animal: The New Science of Evolutionary Psychology , New York: Pantheon.
How to cite this entry . Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society . Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers , with links to its database.
  • Living Links , Center for the Advanced Study of Ape and Human Evolution
  • Living Links , To Human Evolution Research Centre
  • Moral Foundations , Jonathan Haidt’s page on Moral Foundations Theory, UVA

altruism: biological | evolution: cultural | moral psychology: empirical approaches | psychology: evolutionary | religion: and science | sociobiology | Spencer, Herbert

Copyright © 2020 by William FitzPatrick < william . fitzpatrick @ rochester . edu >

  • Accessibility

Support SEP

Mirror sites.

View this site from another server:

  • Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2023 by The Metaphysics Research Lab , Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

Module 3: History of Life

Explain the theory of evolution.

All species of living organisms, from bacteria to baboons to blueberries, evolved at some point from a different species. Although it may seem that living things today stay much the same, that is not the case—evolution is an ongoing process.

The theory of evolution is the unifying theory of biology, meaning it is the framework within which biologists ask questions about the living world. Its power is that it provides direction for predictions about living things that are borne out in experiment after experiment. The Ukrainian-born American geneticist Theodosius Dobzhansky famously wrote that “nothing makes sense in biology except in the light of evolution.” [1] He meant that the tenet that all life has evolved and diversified from a common ancestor is the foundation from which we approach all questions in biology.

Learning Objectives

  • Define natural selection
  • Describe the basis of the present-day theory of evolution
  • Describe how the theory of evolution by natural selection is supported by evidence
  • Refute common misconceptions about evolution

Natural Selection

Darwin and descent with modification.

Illustration shows four different species of finch from the Galápagos Islands. Beak shape ranges from broad and thick to narrow and thin.

Figure 1. Darwin observed that beak shape varies among finch species. He postulated that the beak of an ancestral species had adapted over time to equip the finches to acquire different food sources.

Charles Darwin is best known for his discovery of natural selection. In the mid-nineteenth century, the actual mechanism for evolution was independently conceived of and described by two naturalists: Charles Darwin and Alfred Russel Wallace. Importantly, each naturalist spent time exploring the natural world on expeditions to the tropics. From 1831 to 1836, Darwin traveled around the world on  H.M.S. Beagle , including stops in South America, Australia, and the southern tip of Africa. Wallace traveled to Brazil to collect insects in the Amazon rainforest from 1848 to 1852 and to the Malay Archipelago from 1854 to 1862. Darwin’s journey, like Wallace’s later journeys to the Malay Archipelago, included stops at several island chains, the last being the Galápagos Islands west of Ecuador. On these islands, Darwin observed species of organisms on different islands that were clearly similar, yet had distinct differences. For example, the ground finches inhabiting the Galápagos Islands comprised several species with a unique beak shape (Figure 1).

The species on the islands had a graded series of beak sizes and shapes with very small differences between the most similar. He observed that these finches closely resembled another finch species on the mainland of South America. Darwin imagined that the island species might be species modified from one of the original mainland species. Upon further study, he realized that the varied beaks of each finch helped the birds acquire a specific type of food. For example, seed-eating finches had stronger, thicker beaks for breaking seeds, and insect-eating finches had spear-like beaks for stabbing their prey.

Wallace and Darwin both observed similar patterns in other organisms and they independently developed the same explanation for how and why such changes could take place. Darwin called this mechanism natural selection.  Natural selection , also known as “survival of the fittest,” is the more prolific reproduction of individuals with favorable traits that survive environmental change because of those traits; this leads to evolutionary change.

For example, a population of giant tortoises found in the Galapagos Archipelago was observed by Darwin to have longer necks than those that lived on other islands with dry lowlands. These tortoises were “selected” because they could reach more leaves and access more food than those with short necks. In times of drought when fewer leaves would be available, those that could reach more leaves had a better chance to eat and survive than those that couldn’t reach the food source. Consequently, long-necked tortoises would be more likely to be reproductively successful and pass the long-necked trait to their offspring. Over time, only long-necked tortoises would be present in the population.

Natural selection, Darwin argued, was an inevitable outcome of three principles that operated in nature. First, most characteristics of organisms are inherited, or passed from parent to offspring. Although no one, including Darwin and Wallace, knew how this happened at the time, it was a common understanding. Second, more offspring are produced than are able to survive, so resources for survival and reproduction are limited. The capacity for reproduction in all organisms outstrips the availability of resources to support their numbers. Thus, there is competition for those resources in each generation. Both Darwin and Wallace’s understanding of this principle came from reading an essay by the economist Thomas Malthus who discussed this principle in relation to human populations. Third, offspring vary among each other in regard to their characteristics and those variations are inherited. Darwin and Wallace reasoned that offspring with inherited characteristics which allow them to best compete for limited resources will survive and have more offspring than those individuals with variations that are less able to compete. Because characteristics are inherited, these traits will be better represented in the next generation. This will lead to change in populations over generations in a process that Darwin called descent with modification. Ultimately, natural selection leads to greater adaptation of the population to its local environment; it is the only mechanism known for adaptive evolution.

Papers by Darwin and Wallace (Figure 2) presenting the idea of natural selection were read together in 1858 before the Linnean Society in London. The following year Darwin’s book,  On the Origin of Species, was published. His book outlined in considerable detail his arguments for gradual changes and adaptive survival by natural selection.

Paintings of Charles Darwin and Alfred Wallace are shown.

Figure 2. Both (a) Charles Darwin and (b) Alfred Wallace wrote scientific papers on natural selection that were presented together before the Linnean Society in 1858.

Demonstrations of evolution by natural selection are time consuming and difficult to obtain. One of the best examples has been demonstrated in the very birds that helped to inspire Darwin’s theory: the Galápagos finches. Peter and Rosemary Grant and their colleagues have studied Galápagos finch populations every year since 1976 and have provided important demonstrations of natural selection. The Grants found changes from one generation to the next in the distribution of beak shapes with the medium ground finch on the Galápagos island of Daphne Major. The birds have inherited variation in the bill shape with some birds having wide deep bills and others having thinner bills. During a period in which rainfall was higher than normal because of an El Niño, the large hard seeds that large-billed birds ate were reduced in number; however, there was an abundance of the small soft seeds which the small-billed birds ate. Therefore, survival and reproduction were much better in the following years for the small-billed birds. In the years following this El Niño, the Grants measured beak sizes in the population and found that the average bill size was smaller. Since bill size is an inherited trait, parents with smaller bills had more offspring and the size of bills had evolved to be smaller. As conditions improved in 1987 and larger seeds became more available, the trend toward smaller average bill size ceased.

Theory of Evolution

Natural selection can only take place if there is  variation , or differences, among individuals in a population. Importantly, these differences must have some genetic basis; otherwise, the selection will not lead to change in the next generation. This is critical because variation among individuals can be caused by non-genetic reasons such as an individual being taller because of better nutrition rather than different genes.

Genetic diversity in a population comes from two main mechanisms: mutation and sexual reproduction. Mutation, a change in DNA, is the ultimate source of new alleles, or new genetic variation in any population. The genetic changes caused by mutation can have one of three outcomes on the phenotype. A mutation affects the phenotype of the organism in a way that gives it reduced fitness—lower likelihood of survival or fewer offspring. A mutation may produce a phenotype with a beneficial effect on fitness. And, many mutations will also have no effect on the fitness of the phenotype; these are called neutral mutations. Mutations may also have a whole range of effect sizes on the fitness of the organism that expresses them in their phenotype, from a small effect to a great effect. Sexual reproduction also leads to genetic diversity: when two parents reproduce, unique combinations of alleles assemble to produce the unique genotypes and thus phenotypes in each of the offspring.

A heritable trait that helps the survival and reproduction of an organism in its present environment is called an  adaptation . Scientists describe groups of organisms becoming adapted to their environment when a change in the range of genetic variation occurs over time that increases or maintains the “fit” of the population to its environment. The webbed feet of platypuses are an adaptation for swimming. The snow leopards’ thick fur is an adaptation for living in the cold. The cheetahs’ fast speed is an adaptation for catching prey.

Whether or not a trait is favorable depends on the environmental conditions at the time. The same traits are not always selected because environmental conditions can change. For example, consider a species of plant that grew in a moist climate and did not need to conserve water. Large leaves were selected because they allowed the plant to obtain more energy from the sun. Large leaves require more water to maintain than small leaves, and the moist environment provided favorable conditions to support large leaves. After thousands of years, the climate changed, and the area no longer had excess water. The direction of natural selection shifted so that plants with small leaves were selected because those populations were able to conserve water to survive the new environmental conditions.

The evolution of species has resulted in enormous variation in form and function. Sometimes, evolution gives rise to groups of organisms that become tremendously different from each other. When two species evolve in diverse directions from a common point, it is called divergent evolution. Such  divergent evolution can be seen in the forms of the reproductive organs of flowering plants which share the same basic anatomies; however, they can look very different as a result of selection in different physical environments and adaptation to different kinds of pollinators (Figure 3).

Photo showing a Dense Blazing Star (Liatrus spicata) and a Purple Coneflower (Echinacea purpurea).

Figure 3. Flowering plants evolved from a common ancestor. Notice that the (a) dense blazing star ( Liatrus spicata ) and the (b) purple coneflower ( Echinacea purpurea ) vary in appearance, yet both share a similar basic morphology. (credit a: modification of work by Drew Avery; credit b: modification of work by Cory Zanker)

In other cases, similar phenotypes evolve independently in distantly related species. For example, flight has evolved in both bats and insects, and they both have structures we refer to as wings, which are adaptations to flight. However, the wings of bats and insects have evolved from very different original structures. This phenomenon is called  convergent evolution , where similar traits evolve independently in species that do not share a recent common ancestry. The two species came to the same function, flying, but did so separately from each other.

These physical changes occur over enormous spans of time and help explain how evolution occurs. Natural selection acts on individual organisms, which in turn can shape an entire species. Although natural selection may work in a single generation on an individual, it can take thousands or even millions of years for the genotype of an entire species to evolve. It is over these large time spans that life on earth has changed and continues to change.

Our Modern Understanding

The mechanisms of inheritance, or genetics, were not understood at the time Charles Darwin and Alfred Russel Wallace were developing their idea of natural selection. This lack of understanding was a stumbling block to understanding many aspects of evolution. In fact, the predominant (and incorrect) genetic theory of the time, blending inheritance, made it difficult to understand how natural selection might operate. Darwin and Wallace were unaware of the genetics work done by Austrian monk Gregor Mendel, which was published in 1866, not long after publication of Darwin’s book, On the Origin of Species .

Mendel’s work was rediscovered in the early twentieth century at which time geneticists were rapidly coming to an understanding of the basics of inheritance. Initially, the newly discovered particulate nature of genes made it difficult for biologists to understand how gradual evolution could occur. But over the next few decades genetics and evolution were integrated in what became known as the modern synthesis—the coherent understanding of the relationship between natural selection and genetics that took shape by the 1940s and is generally accepted today.

In sum, the modern synthesis describes how evolutionary processes, such as natural selection, can affect a population’s genetic makeup, and, in turn, how this can result in the gradual evolution of populations and species. The theory also connects this change of a population over time, called microevolution , with the processes that gave rise to new species and higher taxonomic groups with widely divergent characters, called macroevolution .

Evidence of Evolution

The evidence for evolution is compelling and extensive. Looking at every level of organization in living systems, biologists see the signature of past and present evolution. Darwin dedicated a large portion of his book,  On the Origin of Species , to identifying patterns in nature that were consistent with evolution, and since Darwin, our understanding has become clearer and broader.

Physical Evidence

Fossils provide solid evidence that organisms from the past are not the same as those found today, and fossils show a progression of evolution. Scientists determine the age of fossils and categorize them from all over the world to determine when the organisms lived relative to each other. The resulting fossil record tells the story of the past and shows the evolution of form over millions of years (Figure 4a). For example, scientists have recovered highly detailed records showing the evolution of humans and horses (Figure 4b).

Photo A shows a museum display of hominid skulls that vary in size and shape. Illustration B shows five extinct species related and similar in appearance to the modern horse. The species vary in size from that of a modern horse to that of a medium-sized dog.

Figure 4. In this (a) display, fossil hominids are arranged from oldest (bottom) to newest (top). As hominids evolved, the shape of the skull changed. An artist’s rendition of (b) extinct species of the genus Equus reveals that these ancient species resembled the modern horse (Equus ferus) but varied in size.

Anatomy and Embryology

Illustration compares a human arm, dog and bird legs, and a whale flipper. All appendages have the same bones, but the size and shape of these bones vary.

Figure 5. The similar construction of these appendages indicates that these organisms share a common ancestor.

Another type of evidence for evolution is the presence of structures in organisms that share the same basic form. For example, the bones in the appendages of a human, dog, bird, and whale all share the same overall construction (Figure 5) resulting from their origin in the appendages of a common ancestor. Over time, evolution led to changes in the shapes and sizes of these bones in different species, but they have maintained the same overall layout. Scientists call these synonymous parts homologous structures.

Some structures exist in organisms that have no apparent function at all, and appear to be residual parts from a past common ancestor. These unused structures without function are called vestigial structures. Some examples of vestigial structures are wings on flightless birds, leaves on some cacti, and hind leg bones in whales.

Another evidence of evolution is the convergence of form in organisms that share similar environments. For example, species of unrelated animals, such as the arctic fox and ptarmigan, living in the arctic region have been selected for seasonal white phenotypes during winter to blend with the snow and ice (Figure 6). These similarities occur not because of common ancestry, but because of similar selection pressures—the benefits of not being seen by predators.

The left photo depicts an arctic fox with white fur sleeping on white snow, and the right photo shows a ptarmigan with white plumage standing on white snow.

Figure 6. The white winter coat of the (a) arctic fox and the (b) ptarmigan’s plumage are adaptations to their environments. (credit a: modification of work by Keith Morehouse)

Embryology, the study of the development of the anatomy of an organism to its adult form, also provides evidence of relatedness between now widely divergent groups of organisms. Mutational tweaking in the embryo can have such magnified consequences in the adult that embryo formation tends to be conserved. As a result, structures that are absent in some groups often appear in their embryonic forms and disappear by the time the adult or juvenile form is reached. For example, all vertebrate embryos, including humans, exhibit gill slits and tails at some point in their early development. These disappear in the adults of terrestrial groups but are maintained in adult forms of aquatic groups such as fish and some amphibians. Great ape embryos, including humans, have a tail structure during their development that is lost by the time of birth.

Biological Evidence

Biogeography.

The geographic distribution of organisms on the planet follows patterns that are best explained by evolution in conjunction with the movement of tectonic plates over geological time. Broad groups that evolved before the breakup of the supercontinent Pangaea (about 200 million years ago) are distributed worldwide. Groups that evolved since the breakup appear uniquely in regions of the planet, such as the unique flora and fauna of northern continents that formed from the supercontinent Laurasia and of the southern continents that formed from the supercontinent Gondwana. The presence of members of the plant family Proteaceae in Australia, southern Africa, and South America is best due to their appearance prior to the southern supercontinent Gondwana breaking up.

The great diversification of marsupials in Australia and the absence of other mammals reflect Australia’s long isolation. Australia has an abundance of endemic species—species found nowhere else—which is typical of islands whose isolation by expanses of water prevents species migration. Over time, these species diverge evolutionarily into new species that look very different from their ancestors that may exist on the mainland. The marsupials of Australia, the finches on the Galápagos, and many species on the Hawaiian Islands are all unique to their one point of origin, yet they display distant relationships to ancestral species on mainlands.

Molecular Biology

Like anatomical structures, the structures of the molecules of life reflect descent with modification. Evidence of a common ancestor for all of life is reflected in the universality of DNA as the genetic material and in the near universality of the genetic code and the machinery of DNA replication and expression. Fundamental divisions in life between the three domains are reflected in major structural differences in otherwise conservative structures such as the components of ribosomes and the structures of membranes. In general, the relatedness of groups of organisms is reflected in the similarity of their DNA sequences—exactly the pattern that would be expected from descent and diversification from a common ancestor.

DNA sequences have also shed light on some of the mechanisms of evolution. For example, it is clear that the evolution of new functions for proteins commonly occurs after gene duplication events that allow the free modification of one copy by mutation, selection, or drift (changes in a population’s gene pool resulting from chance), while the other copy continues to produce a functional protein.

Evolution—It’s a Thing

This video defines evolution and discusses several varieties of evidence that support the Theory of Evolution:

Misconceptions of Evolution

Although the theory of evolution generated some controversy when it was first proposed, it was almost universally accepted by biologists, particularly younger biologists, within 20 years after publication of  On the Origin of Species . Nevertheless, the theory of evolution is a difficult concept and misconceptions about how it works abound.

Evolution Is Just a Theory

Critics of the theory of evolution dismiss its importance by purposefully confounding the everyday usage of the word “theory” with the way scientists use the word. In science, a “theory” is understood to be a body of thoroughly tested and verified explanations for a set of observations of the natural world. Scientists have a theory of the atom, a theory of gravity, and the theory of relativity, each of which describes understood facts about the world. In the same way, the theory of evolution describes facts about the living world. As such, a theory in science has survived significant efforts to discredit it by scientists. In contrast, a “theory” in common vernacular is a word meaning a guess or suggested explanation; this meaning is more akin to the scientific concept of “hypothesis.” When critics of evolution say evolution is “just a theory,” they are implying that there is little evidence supporting it and that it is still in the process of being rigorously tested. This is a mischaracterization.

Individuals Evolve

Evolution is the change in genetic composition of a population over time, specifically over generations, resulting from differential reproduction of individuals with certain alleles. Individuals do change over their lifetime, obviously, but this is called development and involves changes programmed by the set of genes the individual acquired at birth in coordination with the individual’s environment. When thinking about the evolution of a characteristic, it is probably best to think about the change of the average value of the characteristic in the population over time. For example, when natural selection leads to bill-size change in medium-ground finches in the Galápagos, this does not mean that individual bills on the finches are changing. If one measures the average bill size among all individuals in the population at one time and then measures the average bill size in the population several years later, this average value will be different as a result of evolution. Although some individuals may survive from the first time to the second, they will still have the same bill size; however, there will be many new individuals that contribute to the shift in average bill size.

Organisms Evolve on Purpose

Statements such as “organisms evolve in response to a change in an environment” are quite common, but such statements can lead to two types of misunderstandings. First, the statement must not be understood to mean that individual organisms evolve. The statement is shorthand for “a population evolves in response to a changing environment.” However, a second misunderstanding may arise by interpreting the statement to mean that the evolution is somehow intentional. A changed environment results in some individuals in the population, those with particular phenotypes, benefiting and therefore producing proportionately more offspring than other phenotypes. This results in change in the population if the characteristics are genetically determined.

It is also important to understand that the variation that natural selection works on is already in a population and does not arise in response to an environmental change. For example, applying antibiotics to a population of bacteria will, over time, select a population of bacteria that are resistant to antibiotics. The resistance, which is caused by a gene, did not arise by mutation because of the application of the antibiotic. The gene for resistance was already present in the gene pool of the bacteria, likely at a low frequency. The antibiotic, which kills the bacterial cells without the resistance gene, strongly selects individuals that are resistant, since these would be the only ones that survived and divided. Experiments have demonstrated that mutations for antibiotic resistance do not arise as a result of antibiotic.

In a larger sense, evolution is not goal directed. Species do not become “better” over time; they simply track their changing environment with adaptations that maximize their reproduction in a particular environment at a particular time. Evolution has no goal of making faster, bigger, more complex, or even smarter species, despite the commonness of this kind of language in popular discourse. What characteristics evolve in a species are a function of the variation present and the environment, both of which are constantly changing in a non-directional way. What trait is fit in one environment at one time may well be fatal at some point in the future. This holds equally well for a species of insect as it does the human species.

Evolution Explains the Origin of Life

It is a common misunderstanding that evolution includes an explanation of life’s origins. Conversely, some of the theory’s critics believe that it cannot explain the origin of life. The theory does not try to explain the origin of life. The theory of evolution explains how populations change over time and how life diversifies the origin of species. It does not shed light on the beginnings of life including the origins of the first cells, which is how life is defined. The mechanisms of the origin of life on Earth are a particularly difficult problem because it occurred a very long time ago, and presumably it just occurred once. Importantly, biologists believe that the presence of life on Earth precludes the possibility that the events that led to life on Earth can be repeated because the intermediate stages would immediately become food for existing living things.

However, once a mechanism of inheritance was in place in the form of a molecule like DNA either within a cell or pre-cell, these entities would be subject to the principle of natural selection. More effective reproducers would increase in frequency at the expense of inefficient reproducers. So while evolution does not explain the origin of life, it may have something to say about some of the processes operating once pre-living entities acquired certain properties.

In Summary: Misconceptions of Evolution

Many misconceptions exist about the theory of evolution—including some perpetuated by critics of the theory. First, evolution as a scientific theory means that it has years of observation and accumulated data supporting it. It is not “just a theory” as a person may say in common vernacular.

Another misconception is that individuals evolve, though in fact it is populations that evolve over time. Individuals simply carry mutations. Furthermore, these mutations neither arise on purpose nor do they arise in response to an environmental pressure. Instead, mutations in DNA happen spontaneously and are already present in individuals of a population when a selective pressure occurs. Once the environment begins to favor a particular trait, then those individuals already carrying that mutation will have a selective advantage and are likely to survive better and outproduce others without the adaptation.

Finally, the theory of evolution does not in fact address the origins of life on this planet. Scientists believe that we cannot, in fact, repeat the circumstances that led to life on Earth because at this time life already exists. The presence of life has so dramatically changed the environment that the origins cannot be totally produced for study.

Check Your Understanding

Answer the question(s) below to see how well you understand the topics covered in the previous section. This short quiz does  not  count toward your grade in the class, and you can retake it an unlimited number of times.

Use this quiz to check your understanding and decide whether to (1) study the previous section further or (2) move on to the next section.

  • Theodosius Dobzhansky. “Biology, Molecular and Organismic.” American Zoologist 4, no. 4 (1964): 449. ↵
  • Introduction to Evolution . Authored by : Shelli Carter and Lumen Learning. Provided by : Lumen Learning. License : CC BY: Attribution
  • Biology. Provided by : OpenStax CNX. Located at : http://cnx.org/contents/[email protected] . License : CC BY: Attribution . License Terms : Download for free at http://cnx.org/contents/[email protected]
  • Evolution: It's a Thing - Crash Course Biology #20. Authored by : CrashCourse. Located at : https://youtu.be/P3GagfbA2vo . License : All Rights Reserved . License Terms : Standard YouTube License

COMMENTS

  1. Education Is Life Itself: Biological Evolution as a Model for Human

    between biological evolution and human learning, this essay argues that formal education ... the evolutionary process, no sharp distinction between "preparation for living" and "process of living," nor between "integration" and "freedom," or between "survival" and "liberation." Individual organisms come into existence with a set of tools ...

  2. How evolution learns to generalise: Using the principles of learning

    Author summary A striking feature of evolving organisms is their ability to acquire novel characteristics that help them adapt in new environments. The origin and the conditions of such ability remain elusive and is a long-standing question in evolutionary biology. Recent theory suggests that organisms can evolve designs that help them generate novel features that are more likely to be ...

  3. How learning can change the course of evolution

    Abstract. The interaction between phenotypic plasticity, e.g. learning, and evolution is an important topic both in Evolutionary Biology and Machine Learning. The evolution of learning is commonly studied in Evolutionary Biology, while the use of an evolutionary process to improve learning is of interest to the field of Machine Learning.

  4. How learning can change the course of evolution

    The interaction between phenotypic plasticity, e.g. learning, and evolution is an important topic both in Evolutionary Biology and Machine Learning. The evolution of learning is commonly studied in Evolutionary Biology, while the use of an evolutionary process to improve learning is of interest to the field of Machine Learning. This paper takes a different point of view by studying the effect ...

  5. PDF Embodied intelligence via learning and evolution

    Discussion. The eld of AI, which seeks to reproduce and augment biological fi intelligence, has focused primarily on disembodied learning methods. In contrast, embodied cognition3 -5 posits that ...

  6. An Evolutionary Approach to Motivation and Learning ...

    An evolutionary perspective has been proposed to explain this variation in learning motivation (Geary, 1995; Geary & Xu, 2022a; Marsh et al., 2021).It has been suggested that children are motivated to engage in activities, such as social play or exploration of the environment, that support the development to universal forms of knowledge, such as language and the location of important things (e ...

  7. Tackling the difficulties in learning evolution: effects of adaptive

    Introduction. Evolutionary biology is a consistent principle which unifies all topics in biology (Dobzhansky Citation 1973; Nehm et al. Citation 2009) and explains both the diversity as well as the unity of life (Dobzhansky Citation 1973).Understanding evolutionary theory 'helps us to understand the world around us, our place in it, and ourselves' (Futuyma Citation 1998, 6).

  8. Learning as an evolutionary process

    Learning is not a static concept. It is an evolutionary process. Learning involves creating new ideas out of old ones. It does not mean entirely rejecting what went before, but making new connections and reconfiguring the networks, so that previous knowledge transforms into new knowledge that serves human purposes more adequately than older forms.

  9. Evolutionary Perspectives on Educational Psychology: Motivation

    An evolutionary perspective on academic learning and schooling more generally helps us to understand why learning comes effortlessly in some domains (e.g., language) but only with extensive instruction and cognitive effort in others (e.g., mathematics); why many students' self-concepts are more strongly influenced by physical traits and social relationships than by academic achievement; and ...

  10. Darwin, evolution, & natural selection (article)

    Charles Darwin was a British naturalist who proposed the theory of biological evolution by natural selection. Darwin defined evolution as "descent with modification," the idea that species change over time, give rise to new species, and share a common ancestor. The mechanism that Darwin proposed for evolution is natural selection.

  11. Evolutionary Epistemology

    Evolutionary epistemology is the attempt to address questions in the theory of knowledge from an evolutionary point of view. Evolutionary epistemology involves, in part, deploying models and metaphors drawn from evolutionary biology in the attempt to characterize and resolve issues arising in epistemology and conceptual change.

  12. Education Is Life Itself: Biological Evolution as a Model for Human

    Schooling often rests uneasily on presumed dichotomies between coverage and inquiry, skill development, and creativity. By drawing on the often under-recognized parallels between biological evolution and human learning, this essay argues that formal education needs and ought not to forego the unconscious exploratory processes of informal learning. Rather than posit as natural the cultural ...

  13. Understanding Evolution

    Describe homologous and vestigial structures. Discuss misconceptions about the theory of evolution. Evolution by natural selection describes a mechanism for how species change over time. Scientists, philosophers, researchers, and others had made suggestions and debated this topic well before Darwin began to explore this idea.

  14. Full article: Evolutionary learning processes as the foundation for

    Evolutionary learning process Example of behaviour change method Explanation; Classical conditioning: Providing cues: Assuring that the same cue is present at the time of learning and the time of retrieval facilitates an appropriate response at the time of retrieval, because the cue serves as a conditioned stimulus:

  15. Introduction to Human Evolution

    Human evolution. Human evolution is the lengthy process of change by which people originated from apelike ancestors. Scientific evidence shows that the physical and behavioral traits shared by all people originated from apelike ancestors and evolved over a period of approximately six million years. One of the earliest defining human traits ...

  16. PDF Why does Evolution Matter? The Importance of Understanding Evolution

    Society for Evolutionary Biology in such a paradigmatic place as the Galapagos Islands. The time is ripe to promote evolutionary thought—and science in general—in the Latin American world. It is essential to understand evolution, because everything evolves. Evolution (biological evolution) has become a branch of thought that

  17. How Could Language Have Evolved?

    The evolution of the faculty of language largely remains an enigma. In this essay, we ask why. Language's evolutionary analysis is complicated because it has no equivalent in any nonhuman species. There is also no consensus regarding the essential nature of the language "phenotype.". According to the "Strong Minimalist Thesis," the key ...

  18. Evolutionary Development: A Universal Perspective

    "Evolutionary development," "evo devo" or "ED," is a term that can be used as a replacement for the more general term "evolution," whenever any scholar thinks that both experimental, creative, contingent, stochastic, and increasingly unpredictable or "evolutionary" processes and conservative, convergent, statistically deterministic (probabilistically predictable), or ...

  19. Morality and Evolutionary Biology

    Spencer (1879) conceived of evolution as a teleological process, directed toward the production of progressively "more evolved" (in the sense of "superior") forms manifesting a greater "totality of life", i.e., a greater richness of thought, feeling and action, as well as greater length of life. ... rather than through learning more ...

  20. Introduction to Ecology & Evolutionary Biology

    Evolution by natural selection describes a mechanism for how species change over time. That species change had been suggested and debated well before Darwin began to explore this idea. The view that species were static and unchanging was grounded in the writings of Plato, yet there were also ancient Greeks who expressed evolutionary ideas.

  21. PDF Education Is Life Itself: Biological Evolution as a Model for Human

    recognized parallels between biological evolution and human learning, this essay argues that formal education needs and ought not to forego the unconscious exploratory ... an ongoing evolutionary process in education itself, one in which existing oppositions and problems become the grist from which new approaches emerge. Biology, Evolution, and ...

  22. Essay on Human Evolution: Top 6 Essays

    Essay # 1. Introduction to Human Evolution: Evolution as a process is composed of two parts: 1. An organism reproducing mechanism that provides variable organisms. Changes to the organism are largely random and effect future generations. They are made without regard to consequences to the organism. 2.

  23. Assessing Residential Building Energy Efficiency Using Evolutionary

    Assessing building energy consumption is of paramount significance in sustainability and energy efficiency (EE) studies. The development of an accurate EE prediction model is pivotal for optimizing energy resources and facilitating effective building planning. Traditional physical modeling approaches are encumbered by high complexity and protracted modeling cycles. In this paper, we introduce ...

  24. Evolution

    All species of living organisms, from bacteria to baboons to blueberries, evolved at some point from a different species. Although it may seem that living things today stay much the same, that is not the case—evolution is an ongoing process. The theory of evolution is the unifying theory of biology, meaning it is the framework within which ...